Tag Archives: lucretius

Liber Tertivs: On the Nature of the Soul

Eikas cheers to all! We recently became aware of the book Epicurean Philosophy: An introduction from the “Garden of Athens”, edited / written by Christos Yapijakis, Panagiotis Panagiotopoulos, and others from the Epicurean Gardens in Greece.

The book Epicurus and His Influence on History, by Ben Gazur is available for pre-order. He has, in the past, written the essays An Epicurean Cure and Why Epicurus Matters Today.

This month, Revista Horizonte’s YouTube channel published the lecture “Perspectiva política de la filosofía epicúrea” by Estiven Valencia Marín. This is in Spanish, and the facilitator argues that Epicurean philosophy does not strictly forbid political engagement.

In Mahsa Amini: the new Iphianassa, we discussed that Lucretius opens his poem De rerum natura by giving various reasons for writing the poem, among them the perceived need for a new social contract that was not oppressive because of the corruption of religion. Near the opening, he also mentions that death and the nature of the soul are serious enough threats to human happiness, that they too were reasons for writing his poem.

For what the soul may be they do not know,
Whether ’tis born, or enter in at birth,
And whether, snatched by death, it die with us,
Or visit the shadows …
– Lucretius, De rerum natura, Liber Primus

Ergo, clarifying the nature of the soul is one of the intended purposes of De rerum natura. In the third of the six books, after summarizing Books 1 and 2 (verses 31-33), Lucretius introduces Liber Tertivm, the entirety of which (like Philodemus of Gadara’s wonderful scroll “Peri Thanatos” / “On Death”) contains meleta on Principal Doctrine 2, and which deals with both death and the nature of the soul. In fact, there are some parallels with the Philodeman scroll, and around verse 884 we see Lucretian criticism of being angry that one has to die and of worrying about various ways of dying, which is reminiscent of Peri Thanatos. The reason why he chose this particular subject (as per verses 36-93) is that he says that fear of hell and death lead to degrading or fear-based forms of religion, zeal (fanaticism), evil, greed, murder, and the quest for fame and of other vain and empty desires.

In verse 55, Lucretius says that when men are in doubt or in anger, we get to see what they’re made of, because they tend to use “the mask” of religious zeal. This is a profoundly insightful commentary on the nature of religiosity, and applies a Philodeman logic–where we diagnose some neurosis or what he calls “disease of the soul” based on signs.

Will hate of living and beholding light
Take hold on humankind that they inflict
Their own destruction with a gloomy heart-
Forgetful that this fear is font of cares,
This fear the plague upon their sense of shame,
And this that breaks the ties of comradry
And oversets all reverence and faith …

For just as children tremble and fear all
In the viewless dark, so even we at times
Dread in the light so many things that be
No whit more fearsome than what children feign,
Shuddering, will be upon them in the dark.
This terror, then, this darkness of the mind,
Not sunrise with its flaring spokes of light,
Nor glittering arrows of morning sun disperse,
But only nature’s aspect and her law.

Defining the Natural Soul

Further Reading: The Concrete Self
Lucretius Book 3 – Death of the Soul, and Other Good Things

Epicurus instructs at the opening of his Epistle to Herotodus, that we must first define the object of our investigation, before we begin any discourse. We generally think of the natural soul as the condition of the living flesh that gives us life and sentience. As Epicureans, we are unconcerned with any supernatural or Platonic conception of the soul. Instead, we speak of the nature of the soul, even of the health of the soul, in wholly physical terms. Lucretius defined the soul as part of the body, and connects it with the head or the intellect from where the organism governs itself.

The mind (animus / sometimes translated as soul) which oft we call the intellect (mentem), wherein is seated life’s counsel and regimen, is part no less of man than hand and foot and eyes are parts of one whole breathing creature. – Liber Tertivs, 94-95

In Liber Tertivs, Lucretius is expounding the same theories that Epicurus expounds in his Letter to Herodotus (portions 63-68), and in more detail. To be clear, the soul is physical. Lucretius explains that the soul is mortal (416, 603-614) and that it gets sick and ages with the body (445-491), that wine gets the soul drunk, and that the soul’s diseases can be treated with medicine (510-525). We also learn that the soul has no weight (230), that the five senses are among the soul’s faculties (624-633), and that the first atomists imagined that the atoms of the soul were particularly subtle or tiny because neural activity happens so fast (177-205), and in this he uses the analogy of how water moves faster than honey because it’s less dense.

Must we not grant that mind and soul consist of a corporeal nature? – 167

The Head, the Chest, and the Belly

Mind and soul (animum atque animam), I say, are held conjoined one with other, and form one single nature of themselves; but chief (caput) and regnant through the frame entire is still that counsel which we call the mind, and that cleaves seated in the midmost breast.

“Caput” means “head”, and indicates that the soul is the head of the body. He may have been working with, and translating from, the Greek word “psyche” in his sources.

Lucretius argues (147-160, and again in 395-415) that the mind is stronger than the flesh. This idea of the soul as the head of the body echoes the logic of Principal Doctrine 20, which we also find in the Wall Inscription of Oenoanda.

Emotions in antiquity were associated with the chest, so it’s not surprising that the ancient Epicureans believed the soul was partially in the chest. This is likely based on the process of “reasoning by signs”, and the observation that strong emotions increase the heart rate and that the heart stops beating at the moment of death. In reality, as Lucretius explains elsewhere, the soul or animating power is found embedded throughout the entire bodily frame.

The focus on the chest as seat of the natural soul might be part of the Epicureans’ insistence that man is more than a rational animal, that he has irrational faculties that are just as important as reason. Lucretius mentions some of these non-rational feelings and faculties of the soul (joy, terror, dismay, etc.)

There are many instinctive psychological processes that happen in the belly, and we know that many of the so-called “happiness hormones” are synthesized in the belly as well. Some yoga instructors teach focused exercises for what they call the “solar plexus”. Some (like Osho)–in a manner that may remind some of Metrodorus’ arguments with his brother–insist that we must “befriend the belly”. Current research shows that the belly has enough neurons to constitute a “second brain”

I do not wish to digress much into Taoism, but I wish to accentuate that one of its founders–Yang Chu, who was hugely influential among the Seven Sages of the Bamboo Grove and many other later thinkers–based his entire philosophy on the body as our ultimate ontology. He is the author of several chapters of the second most important classic in Taoism, the Zhuang Tzu. The lack of a Platonic split between body and soul in Taoism has produced a vibrant philosophy that expresses itself in bodily practices related to preventive health, movement, and martial arts, with no boundary whatsoever between the so-called spiritual world and the body.

In Taoist martial arts and meditative practices, the belly is the focus of attention and breath-work, and considered an important means of grounding an stabilizing oneself. The belly, together with certain dietary practices, are important in other cultures’ regimens of self-care.

Treatments for Fear of Death

The main utility of studying the nature of the physical soul is to produce a theory and practice that works, and that can provide treatments for fear of death. These treatments, for the Epicureans, usually focus on arguments, repetition, placing before the eyes, and other similar techniques.

One such argument from Liber Tertivs (verse 904) consists of comparing death to being asleep. Another one is the symmetry argument, which compares the time after death with the time before birth of which we remember nothing, and so there is nothing to fear.

Other arguments are less therapeutic, and more about giving a more complete account of the nature of death in the context of our inter-existence with the other bodies that make up the cosmos. For instance, Lucretius says (in 970) that one thing grows from another, and since all bodies need the particles of other bodies in order to subsist, therefore we must accept that life is a loan.

Lucretian Reassessment of Myths

A naturalist redefinition of the soul and of death has the domino effect of dismantling much of the vulgar mythology that our ancestors have built around them. Lucretius argues that hell is on Earth, that Tartarus is not a place under the ground but represents fear of the gods and of fate, that Tityus is about the dangers of quick care and vague desire, and that the Sisyphus myth (which we discuss below) is about the tendency to seek power even if it does not add pleasure, which feels as if we were pushing a boulder up a hill.

The bottom line is that there is NO other world or afterlife, and that the only relevance of these myths is found in this world.

The Jar Parable

Although the Punctured Jar parable is treated in Liber Sextvs, in the third book we see that the imagery of the jar is an ongoing theme in Lucretius. Here, the body is compared to a jar that cracks open at the time of death and releases its vitality (verses 434-444). Around verse 793 we read that the mind requires the body as a “vessel”, again refuting the idea that a soul may exist without a host body. That the mind needs the body as a vessel is again mentioned around verse 555:

And just as hand, or eye, or nose, apart,
Severed from us, can neither feel nor be,
But in the least of time is left to rot,
Thus mind alone can never be, without
The body and the man himself, which seems,
As ’twere the vessel of the same- or aught
Whate’er thou’lt feign as yet more closely joined:
Since body cleaves to mind by surest bonds.

It seems like the punctured jar parable was part of a long string of meditations and parables on the physical nature of the soul, which in Liber Sextvs culminates in a salvific teaching.

Around verse 1000, while discussing the myth of Sisyphus, Lucretius makes another reference to the idea of the soul as a jar when he compared Sisyphus’ pushing a stone uphill to the behavior of someone who “feeds forever a thankless heart with good things yet never fills it”.

Here in this life also a Sisyphus
In him who seeketh of the populace
The rods, the axes fell, and evermore
Retires a beaten and a gloomy man.
For to seek after power- an empty name,
Nor given at all- and ever in the search
To endure a world of toil, O this it is
To shove with shoulder up the hill a stone
Which yet comes rolling back from off the top,
And headlong makes for levels of the plain.
Then to be always feeding an ingrate mind,
Filling with good things, satisfying never-
As do the seasons of the year for us,
When they return and bring their progenies
And varied charms, and we are never filled
With the fruits of life- O this, I fancy, ’tis
To pour, like those young virgins in the tale,
Waters into a sieve, unfilled forever.

In the jar metaphor, Lucretius is using poetic imagery as an expedient means to instruct us on the nature of the soul and its need for philosophy, while still employing poetry, parables, and myths. He does not dismiss these cultural devices, but employs them according to the study of nature. In doing this, Lucretius helps to construct a new spirituality, one that is fully physical and consistent with the scientific worldview and with the study of nature, but yet does not reject storytelling, poetry, imagery, parables, etc. In other words, he’s continuing Epicurus’ project of elaborating a complete worldview and cosmology–from the elemental particles all the way to the innumerable worlds–that yet satisfies and cares for the soul and all of its existential needs.

Further Reading:

The Concrete Self

The Punctured Jar Parable

Happy Twentieth: The Lucretian Parable of the Alphabet

Eikas cheers to all! Speaking of the Twentieth feast–this month, Paste magazine published the essay Eikas: The Dinner Party as Philosophy. The author makes the case that traditions like the Twentieth feast help to keep us human, rooted, and connected (particularly during the pandemic).

Our Friend Nate has added his compilation of multiple translations of the Kyriai Doxai in academia.edu as Key Doctrines of Epicurus. This is the most comprehensive compilation of translations of the PDs available.

Other literary updates include the Medium essay Epicurean philosophy as a way of life in Antiquity, and someone found a figurine from that Roman Era in England that they believe is Epicurus: Finds tray – Epicurus figurine.

The Lucretian Parable of the Alphabet

Nunc age dicta meo dulci quaesita labore percipe.

Come now and hear the words I chose with joy and care.

– Lucretius, De rerum natura, Liber Secvndvs, 730

In Atomic Poetics: Lucretius’ De Rerum Natura, Gwendolyn Gruber says:

Atoms are like letters, Lucretius explains in Book 2 of De Rerum Natura. The finite number of various atomic shapes combine to create all the different things in the universe, just as the letters of the alphabet can be recombined in a variety of ways to create different words … This analogy can also be applied to Lucretius’ poetic endeavor. Just as the atoms join to make objects, Lucretius puts letters together to create words, and words together to create poetry. Just as combinations of atoms join to make large things, including the universe, Lucretius connects words and verses to produce a grand epic. In writing De Rerum Natura, Lucretius mimics the activity of the atoms and the poem’s structure can be viewed as a metaphor for Epicurean atomic theory.

As an author and word-smith, I’ve always loved the parable of the alphabet in De rerum natura. In the pen of Lucretius, the elements of nature create poetry, art, medicine, knowledge, values, meaning, and all the other things that letters can create. Nature makes art in the pen of Lucretius. Nature (which includes us) makes culture and artifice in the pen of Lucretius. Here are the relevant passages:

Nay, here in these our verses,
Elements many, common to many words,
Thou seest, though yet ’tis needful to confess
The words and verses differ, each from each,
Compounded out of different elements-
Not since few only, as common letters, run
Through all the words, or no two words are made,
One and the other, from all like elements,
But since they all, as general rule, are not
The same as all. Thus, too, in other things,
Whilst many germs common to many things
There are, yet they, combined among themselves,
Can form new wholes to others quite unlike.

– De rerum natura, Liber Secvndvs, 708-720

And again:

Why, even in these our very verses here
It matters much with what and in what order
Each element is set: the same denote
Sky, and the ocean, lands, and streams, and sun;
The same, the grains, and trees, and living things.
And if not all alike, at least the most-
But what distinctions by positions wrought!
And thus no less in things themselves, when once
Around are changed the intervals between,
The paths of matter, its connections, weights,
Blows, clashings, motions, order, structure, shapes,
The things themselves must likewise changed be.

– De rerum natura, Liber Secvndvs, 1012-1022

Lucretius returned more than once to the metaphor of the alphabet. It had been mentioned casually in Liber Primvs 196-198:

Thus easier ’tis to hold that many things
Have primal bodies in common (as we see
The single letters common to many words)
Than aught exists without its origins.

Now, in order to understand how brilliant this Lucretian parable is, and how it relates to the physics of Epicurus, we must understand that in his Epistle to Herodotus (tmíma/portion 42 in the Laertian division system), Epicurus asserts that there is an infinite number of atoms, but that these atoms assume a finite variety and number of possible combinations.

Furthermore, the atoms, which have no void in them–out of which composite bodies arise and into which they are dissolved–vary indefinitely in their shapes; for so many varieties of things as we see could never have arisen out of a recurrence of a definite number of the same shapes. The like atoms of each shape are absolutely infinite; but the variety of shapes, though indefinitely large, is not absolutely infinite.

Later, in De rerum natura, Liber Secvndvs, 496-499, Lucretius reiterates this by arguing that if elemental particles had infinite varieties of shapes, some of them would be visible to the naked eye, which is not what we observe:

Therefore you have no right to think atoms may vary indefinitely in shape; else you may force some to assume portentous vastness–but this I’ve shown cannot be true.

These particular portions of the Epistle to Herodotus and DRN are the thought-provoking key to developing a clear understanding of the Doctrine of Innumerable Worlds, and Epicurean cosmology in general, but in this essay I’d like to focus on the parable itself.

Nature’s Grammar

Just as each alphabetical system only has on average somewhere between 20-30 letters (“the atomic elements” within the parable) which must be combined to make words, similarly the laws of nature only allow for certain types of particles, and certain forms of atomic combinations:

  • We see that the size and behavior of gas, ocean, and rocky planets depend on factors like access to solar light, pressure, distance from their star, mass accrued, and elements contained. Planets are not rocky if they grow beyond a certain size.
  • We see that each element behaves differently at diverse temperatures: water acts as ice or gas at certain degrees, and so do other elements, which is why on Earth we have a water-ocean and in Titan there are lakes of methane at freezing temperatures.
  • We see that different elements interact differently with each other, some joining together and others repelling each other, according to their properties, etc.

The limits of what is possible are set by the elemental particles and their possible combinations. In this way, the limits set by nature allow us to perceive order in the cosmos and to articulate scientific truths.

In Lucretius’ pen, nature has a grammar. Sometimes elements interact in a manner that is active or dynamic (forming something like a verb within a sentence, which carries the action). Sometimes two bodies interact so that they change each other, like an adjective changes a noun. Sometimes their interaction is so dramatic that they form a new compound word, in the same way that in lichen life-forms, fungi and algae become a single symbiotic life-form-system. The preceding simple nouns have combined.

The rules of nature’s grammar are pragmatically discernible just as our language faculty allow us to make words discernible to us. If you say “QYTP” to someone who speaks Spanish, that person will not make sense of what you’ve said because this particular combination of letters does not produce meaning in Spanish. If you say “sol”, or “luna”, that person will understand that you speak of the sun and the moon because this particular combination of letters produces those meanings. The natural elements are like these letters within the language in which we can read nature.

The idea of nature’s grammar reminds me of the four “letters” that we find in the double strand of DNA: G, T, C, A. They’re not “letters”, they’re molecules, but they operate like letters to create information in our cells, and scientists have always casually compared them to and treated them as letters. They’re only four, and their possible combinations are strictly limited, yet together they form a wonderful variety of life.

One of the things that Lucretius is saying in this parable, is that we can find “meaning” in  the study of nature and in the realism it unveils (since meaning can only be expressed in signs in some way, which are constituted by these elemental “letters”). When in Liber Tertivs, Lucretius explains how scents and chemicals travel in the air and are picked up by the nose, he poetically refers to these particles as “winged words”.

This parable aligns with the Epicurean Guides’ insistence that our words must correspond clearly with the nature of things. This insistence necessitates the conviction that it is indeed possible to express the true nature of things in human language. This belief is part of the philosophical foundation on which this parable stands, and is attested elsewhere in Epicurean writings, even if the methodology needed for this is sometimes admittedly problematic.

An Anti-Skeptic Commentary

Parables are useful, but they cannot replace the true nature of things. One difference between our alphabets and the elements is that, unlike the letters of the alphabet, the elements are not subject to cultural or philosophical relativism. Gravity will always pull our bodies down. H2O molecules will always behave and exist as water in nature’s grammar.

I read in this parable a positive statement of the possibility of pragmatic knowledge–an assertion that we can, indeed, articulate the nature of things with the use of conventional language. This makes it possible to have established scientific theories, as well as orthodox beliefs about the nature of things that are based on the evidence and the study of nature.

One ethically-significant value that is contained in this belief is intellectual honesty, which is essential in an evidence-based philosophical system like ours. To an Epicurean, defense of this belief constitutes a defense of intellectual honesty–which is to say, trust in the evidence of nature, and clarity of speech.

This belief in the possibility of knowledge was and is still rejected by committed Skeptics, who argue that words (signs, to linguists) are not the same as the things they name (signifiers). This is true: language is a cognitive means to apprehend the nature of things. But only mystics and magicians claim that the word is the thing meant: words are signs that refer to the things that are meant or signified. Notice that the prolepsis of the word “signify” (signi-ficare, “sign-making” in verb form) implies that the things that are meant are made into signs. Language is a sign-making technology.

The Epicureans have always insisted on clear speech. Language must be clear in order to fulfill its utility. The concrete signs we use must align clearly with the nature of things.

We also insist that our meaning-making faculty of conceptualization (prolepsis) is part of the Canon, or standard of truth. Since the prolepsis of words derives from an original attestation, words reliably denote something that was at one point empirically available to someone, and words therefore can have empirical and pragmatic origins.

This is not to say that we deny the difficulties we sometimes encounter in this challenge to speak clearly. Case studies concerning the incorrect use of language led the original Epicureans to a process of language reform in the service of clarity, and influenced a “third stage of language development” within the Epicurean theory of language, where philosophers, and experts in various fields of knowledge, develop methods by which they apply the prolepsis of common language to the coining of new words of specialized abstract, scientific, or ethical utility.

An Anti-Nihilist Commentary

Since Epicurus says that philosophy that does not cure the soul is no better than medicine that does not heal the body, we apply the therapeutic interpretation to our sources in order to gain insights about the utility of the Doxai of the Epicurean Guides. This parable contains, in my view, philosophical medicine for the type of nihilism that rejects all values. It argues an ontological realism that says that we have the faculty to discern truths and values in nature. Whatever difficulties we may find in this activity do not justify giving up on the task of articulating the nature of things using language.

Let us use a case study to see how the ethics and physics intersect in our system, producing ethical values from the study of nature that must be part of our hedonic calculus, of our choices and rejections. The value of water is undeniable for humans: we can live without food for 21 days, but we can only survive no more than three days without water. The “value” of H2O is, therefore, not culturally relative. In our bodies, the absence of H2O is experienced as a pain of lack (thirst, and other symptoms in an advance stage), while we observe that a natural measure of the presence of it is experienced as health, vitality, and pleasure. The pleasures and pains produced by H2O molecules in our bodies (or lack thereof) are not a matter of debate, but of physical observation. Access to water is a natural and necessary desire. Each human being needs a certain amount of water to survive. This is why all ancient civilizations emerged alongside water sources and rivers.

Valid and true philosophical and scientific statements that help us to form clear and unerring models of the nature of things have tangible, pragmatic value for how we live and how we plan our lives and communities. We are entering a dangerous time of restricted access to water resources in many places, where the distinction between the necessary desires and unnecessary or arbitrary ones will become painfully clear to many. There’s talk of water wars in the future (although the water wars have already happened in places like Bolivia), and access to this basic resource will increasingly become a prominent economic, ethical and political issue in the coming decades.

Thanks to the constitution of our bodies and our particular faculties, certain values exist in nature. In this way, the Epicurean “study of nature” has an acidic effect on nihilism (if you’ll indulge my chemistry metaphor), if nihilism is defined as the complete absence of definite and clear values.

The Elements of Right Living

There is another way in which this philosophical application of physics insights in the realm of ethics fights nihilism: it creates concrete pleasures, values, and meaning. Epicurus refers to the contents of his Epistle to Menoeceus as comprising the “elements of right living” … which–just like the elements of nature–must be incorporated and constituted together, so that we live ethical and pleasant lives.

Small things show the likeness of larger and the steps that lead to knowledge. – Lucretius, De rerum natura, Liber Secvndvs, 123-124

Elements combine to form bodies of greater and greater complexity, which in turn at greater magnitudes show specific emergent properties. Similarly, large projects must be tackled in the details, in the small things, day by day, moment by moment. Great works are not completed in a day. By applying this model of elemental combination–and the emergence paradigm–to our choices and rejections, to how we plan our lives, we may more efficiently accomplish great works in the long term.

Norman DeWitt ascribed the following proverb to Epicurean philosophy: “The unplanned life is not worth living“. Even philosophers of nihilistic tendency, like many Existentialists, argue that we can create meaning and value by enacting existential projects that render our lives pleasant, meaningful, and complete. Planning requires concrete combinations of many elements.

A Grammar of Salvific Pleasure

The self-referential comparison of the verses in De rerum natura to honey in Liber Qvartvs 9-25 means to sweeten the harsh medicine of philosophy, points to pleasure / sweetness as an ethical point of reference, and asserts that it is possible to combine elemental letters into philosophical and ethical medicine. Here is the Lucretian passage:

First, since I teach concerning mighty things,
And go right on to loose from round the mind
The tightened coils of dread religion;
Next, since, concerning themes so dark, I frame
Song so pellucid, touching all throughout
Even with the Muses’ charm- which, as ‘twould seem,
Is not without a reasonable ground:
For as physicians, when they seek to give
Young boys the nauseous wormwood, first do touch
The brim around the cup with the sweet juice
And yellow of the honey, in order that
The thoughtless age of boyhood be cajoled
As far as the lips, and meanwhile swallow down
The wormwood’s bitter draught, and, though befooled,
Be yet not merely duped, but rather thus
Grow strong again with recreated health:
So now I too (since this my doctrine seems
In general somewhat woeful unto those
Who’ve had it not in hand, and since the crowd
Starts back from it in horror) have desired
To expound our doctrine unto thee in song
Soft-speaking and Pierian, and, as ’twere,
To touch it with sweet honey of the Muse-
If by such method haply I might hold
The mind of thee upon these lines of ours,
Till thou dost learn the nature of all things
And understandest their utility.

This passage concerns the nature of true and therapeutic philosophy itself, which is concretely made up of these words that Lucretius has smeared in poetic honey. He elsewhere refers to Epicurus’ words as “Aurea Dicta” (golden words … worthy of immortal life), and compares them to ambrosia, the nectar of immortality.

In Vatican Saying 41, the Scholarch Hermarchus outlines a practice that involves concrete utterances being spoken out-loud (phonás aphientas, scattered sounds). Philodemus, too, said that the medicine of true philosophy is found in its healing words. Since the Epicurean Guides have an agenda of healing the souls, the parable of the alphabet is more than a passive contemplation of theory: it’s a dynamic part of a salvific toolkit. Epicurus and Lucretius are like shamanic guides who combine letters and words to make philosophical cures for the soul.

In the pen of Lucretius, poetry can be more than poetry. Art can be more than art. Some word combinations may heal nihilistic tendencies, or cure our fears. They may have a superior potency, a medicinal use, but there’s nothing mystical about them: they’re still made up of the same elemental letters as every other word.

The Punctured Jar Parable

Divine Pleasure, the Guide of life, persuades mortality and leads it on that, through her artful blandishments of love, it propagate the generations still, lest humankind should perish. – Lucretius, De Rerum Natura II.172

I’ve been enjoying the pleasures of reading Lucretius’ classic On the Nature of Things (De Rerum Natura), and will be blogging based on it in the future. I’m concerned today with Lucretius’ approach to therapeutic philosophy and to the pursuit of happiness as exemplified in his parable of the punctured jar.

The parable presents Epicurus as a Doctor that heals the ills of the soul. Like all good physicians, he must evaluate the symptoms and determine what the spiritual health problem is. The Frank Copley translation of DRN is much more eloquent in describing the existential situation of an ungrateful, unphilosophical mortal, linking her anxieties to a pervasive, untreated, and unevaluated fear of death.

Will you hang back, indignant that you must die: alive and awake, you live next door to death; you waste the greater part of life in sleep, and even waking, you snore, and dream, dream on; you wear a heart confounded by empty fears. You rarely can tell what caused them when, oppressed and drunk and wretched with unremitting cares, you wander, waver, and wonder where to turn.

Notice the Buddhist-like reference to wakeful dreaming. What is expected of a philosopher is a kind of awakening, of mindfulness, a way of paying attention. Let’s not think of this as a state (a noun, which often Platonizes what’s meant) but as a verb (an activity). We must be present in order to savor life.

In the parable, which is meant to serve as therapy for existential angst and fear of death, Mother Nature advises mortals to be ready to leave this world as one who has enjoyed a banquet and is satisfied. Satisfaction and gratitude are important ingredients in the cultivation of ataraxia. In the banquet passage, Lucretius places words on the lips of Mother Nature:

“Mortal, what hast thou of such grave concern
That thou indulgest in too sickly plaints?
Why this bemoaning and beweeping death?
For if thy life aforetime and behind
To thee was grateful, and not all thy good
Was heaped as in sieve to flow away
And perish unavailingly, why not,
Even like a banqueter, depart the halls,
Laden with life? why not with mind content
Take now, thou fool, thy unafflicted rest?
But if whatever thou enjoyed hath been
Lavished and lost, and life is now offence,
Why seekest more to add- which in its turn
Will perish foully and fall out in vain?
O why not rather make an end of life,
Of labour? For all I may devise or find
To pleasure thee is nothing: all things are
The same forever. Though not yet thy body
Wrinkles with years, nor yet the frame exhausts
Outworn, still things abide the same, even if
Thou goest on to conquer all of time
With length of days, yea, if thou never diest”

In the text, Lucretius argues that if we were to live forever, eventually the pleasures that the Earth has to offer would be all the same. There would be no new experiences, and therefore we should feel sated at the end of a good life.

Ungratefulness to life, to nature, to time, is on the other hand a mortal sin to the Epicurean philosopher. The William Leonard translation does not express it as beautifully as the Frank Copley one, which says: “you wanted what isn’t, scorned what is … life slipped through your fingers shapeless and unlovely“.

What’s being said here is that life is full of many kinds of blessings, but when we are mindless and ungrateful it’s as if we are walking through life with a punctured jar. The water in the punctured jar drains off and the blessings are squandered. With the help of Epicurus, we can train ourselves to make the vessel whole again so that we are enjoying the fullness of the blessings that life has to offer at all times.

In Book VI, his final one, Lucretius picks up the metaphor again, saying that when we fail to experience life’s pleasures, the “fault must lie within the vessel”, with the broken vessel image representing our own souls. The idea of our brokenness would be usurped by the Christians to build a guilt-based theology. In Epicurus and Lucretius, the goal is therapeutic.

For when saw he that well-nigh everything
Which needs of man most urgently require
Was ready to hand for mortals, and that life,
As far as might be, was established safe,
That men were lords in riches, honour, praise,
And eminent in goodly fame of sons,
And that they yet, O yet, within the home,
Still had the anxious heart which vexed life
Unpausingly with torments of the mind,
And raved perforce with angry plaints, then he,
Then he, the master, did perceive that ’twas
The vessel itself which worked the bane, and all,
However wholesome, which from here or there
Was gathered into it, was by that bane
Spoilt from within,- in part, because he saw
The vessel so cracked and leaky that nowise
‘T could ever be filled to brim; in part because
He marked how it polluted with foul taste
Whate’er it got within itself. So he,
The master, then by his truth-speaking words,
Purged the breasts of men, and set the bounds
Of lust and terror, and exhibited
The supreme good whither we all endeavour,
And showed the path whereby we might arrive
Thereunto by a little cross-cut straight …. And he proved
That mostly vainly doth the human race
Roll in its bosom the grim waves of care.
For just as children tremble and fear all
In the viewless dark, so even we at times
Dread in the light so many things that be
No whit more fearsome than what children feign,
Shuddering, will be upon them in the dark.
This terror then, this darkness of the mind,
Not sunrise with its flaring spokes of light,
Nor glittering arrows of morning can disperse,
But only nature’s aspect and her law.

Epicurean philosophy, therefore, is meant to help cleanse our souls by speaking truth, and by limiting our desires and fears through exposure to the study of nature, and by establishing clearly that life’s goal is happiness, and by which methods we most efficiently arrive at happiness: Epicurus gave us a science of happiness.

Today is the International Day of Happiness. Isolation and depression are proven health risks, epidemics on par with obesity and smoking. A smart mortal would never leave something as sacred and important as his or her happiness to the whims of fortune and chance. Happiness is a path best trod mindfully and in good company. Please share philosophical literature and content with your friends today and take care to restore your own punctured vessel via a philosophical education. You may also enjoy deep-belly laughter exercises for fifteen minutes … or share something funny online, or call a friend who is a clown and always makes you laugh. Whatever you do, don’t postpone your happiness today!

Naturalist Reasoning on Friendship

And when they saw an offspring born
From out themselves, then first the human race
Began to soften. For ’twas now that fire
Rendered their shivering frames less staunch to bear,
Under the canopy of the sky, the cold;
And Love reduced their shaggy hardiness;
And children, with the prattle and the kiss,
Soon broke the parents’ haughty temper down.
Then, too, did neighbours ‘gin to league as friends,
Eager to wrong no more or suffer wrong,
And urged for children and the womankind
Mercy, of fathers, whilst with cries and gestures
They stammered hints how meet it was that all
Should have compassion on the weak. And still,
Though concord not in every wise could then
Begotten be, a good, a goodly part
Kept faith inviolate- or else mankind
Long since had been unutterably cut off,
And propagation never could have brought
The species down the ages.

Lucretius, in De Rerum Natura 5:1015-27

Lucretius’ account of how friendship emerged in the human race as a result of its softening and civilizing reminds me of comparative behavioral studies concerning the two species of chimpanzee. The better known species of chimpanzee is aggressive and its tribes and clans are governed by strong, feared alpha males who compete and fight over resources, over the right to mate, and over domination. The other species, the affable bonobos, like to make love instead of war. They solve all their conflicts through sexual exchanges, prefer to cooperate and share resources (again, always using sex as the social lubricant), and their societies are more egalitarian. It has been noted that the bonobos evolved in parts of the African forests where there were plenty of resources to share, whereas the evolution of the traditional chimp saw more scarcity, ergo their more violent nature.

Some of the most violent species of baboons, by way of contrast, experience so much stress during their short lifetimes that they’re in constant state of alert and their health suffers greatly as a result. Humans in overpopulated cities, and those in areas with high levels of poverty, tend also to exhibit higher rates of violent crime whereas wealthier societies exhibit lower rates of violence.

Because examples of both war and cooperation exist among our closest relatives, it’s difficult to discern whether our instances of war and cooperation are the result of nurture or nature. But it can not be denied that similar behavioral patters are found among humans and chimpanzees. We also have our authoritarian alpha males with their docile clans, and elsewhere our open and egalitarian bonobo-like societies.

It should perhaps be asked whether the fact that Abrahamic religions emerged from the desert (no doubt one of the most inhospitable and unfruitful places on Earth) may help to explain the authoritarian and patriarchal alpha-male tendencies in Abrahamic religions. But then, what are we to make of our philosophy of the Garden, a place of fruitfulness and greenery, particularly in contrast with spiritualities of the desert? It’s interesting to note that our Garden tradition emerged in glorification of the pleasures of friendship, the most egalitarian model of human interaction and that its most outstanding cultural expression, the gathering on the 20th, is an exuberant display of plenty, of abundance.

In light of this, we can understand why a Garden philosophy must be a philosophy of autarchy (self-sufficiency), and how self-sufficiency produces friendly humans just as plenty in the African bush produces affectionate bonobos. Without autarchy, we must either depend on others (and build hierarchies based on production and exploitation) or steal from them (engage in pillaging, plunder and violence). With self-sufficiency, we are free from the anxieties that arise when we can’t provide our natural needs and we can easily relate to others affectionately and as trusting equals.

Lucretius said it well: Philos reduced our shaggy hardiness and neighbors began to league as friends eager to wrong no more or be wronged.

The above article first appeared in the May 2014 issue of Happy 20th!

Back to the Main Page

Tweet This