Category Archives: epicurus

The Doctrine of Immortal Goods

“For people lose all appearance of mortality by living in the midst of immortal goods (athanatoi agathoi).” – Epicurus in his Epistle to Menoeceus

“I’ll think of you as an immortal, and you think of us as immortals!” – Epicurus, to Colotes

As we continue our deliberations about the meleta portion of the Epistle to Menoeceus (about which I’ve already written two essays here and here), the concept of “immortal goods” has come up for deepening.

Furthermore, the passage links the immortal goods to the “surroundings” or “ambience” of someone who is living a godlike lifestyle. This is because the life state of each sentient being is contextual to its environment. What are the surroundings of one who lives like an immortal?

Friends as Immortal Goods

The first and least controversial item that belongs in the official list of immortal goods is our friends. We know this with certainty because:

The noble soul occupies itself with wisdom and friendship; of these the one is a mortal good, the other immortal. – Epicurean Saying 78

VS 78 says that friendship is immortal, and wisdom is not. Therefore, in our sources, friends are the only thing that are clearly included among the “immortal goods” mentioned in the Epistle to Menoeceus, and each one of our true friends may therefore serve as a case study to better understand the doctrine of immortal goods.

So following this interpretation, we live like gods if we are surrounded by our friends, each of whom is an immortal good, and we should treat our Epicurean true friends as immortal goods–so long as we remember them with gratitude, they ARE part of us and, in some way, immortal.

Worthy of Immortal Life

The idea of “Athanatoi agathoi” is expressed differently in De rerum Natura. Rather than say there are eternal goods, Lucretius mentions that some things are or aren’t “worthy of immortality“, attaching an “immortal quality” to the worth or value of the thing it describes, as if there was a transcendental quality that makes some things have more value than others.

Philodemus also laments that people give worship to things that are not at all “worthy of immortality and blessedness”. It’s clear that, to the Epicurean Guides throughout history, the Doctrine of Immortal Goods has served as an invitation to deliberate about what things are worthy of immortality, and to deliberate about values. What do you think is worthy of immortality?

If each one of our true friends is, to us, either “worthy of immortal life” or an immortal good (“athanatois agathois“), and if we wish to place before our eyes the ways in which our truest friends are immortal, we should consider what makes them our closest friends. What advantages and pleasures do we share with them? The two undeniable attributes of the Epicurean gods in our writings are invulnerability and bliss: how do our friends contribute to this?

The Pleasures and Fearlessness of the Gods

When I asked about possible interpretations of “athanatoi agathoi” in the Garden group on FB, one of the members (Beryl) said: “I saw this phrase as pertaining to the letter as a whole as meaning (that) when one has rooted out fear of death then it’s as if one is immortal. When one has understanding of nature, one can simply (be) satisfied so as to enjoy life with no suffering as if one is immortal. When one has retired from the hurley-burley of the throng or understands one’s true reasons for involvement, one’s mind is peaceful even amongst storms like an immortal being. I thought the important word is appearance. Folk are still mortal, however, releasing fear and creating an ease full path for satisfying one’s necessary needs gives the peace of mind of an immortal.”

So in this interpretation of “immortal goods”, it’s the mental state and the existential achievement of calm and tranquil abiding that gives mortals the appearance of godliness.

The Theory of Pleasant Remembrance

In Epicurean ethics, visualization (the “placing before the eyes” exercise) and the use of happy memories (the “pleasant remembrance” exercise) are useful ethical practices. The full theory behind them is beyond the scope of this essay, but it is clear that memory plays an important part in how we practice them.

One way to unpack why true friends are considered “immortal” is to think that they are sources of ongoing bliss and pleasure, at least for as long as we remain grateful and remember them. In fact, any object of enjoyment that we practice “pleasant remembrance” with is, to some extent, experienced as immortal or undying.

Experiences and friends around whom we have built pleasant memories are, by definition, memorable, and since the pleasure continues for as long as we are grateful, they are in some way “immortal goods”.

Once we have carried out the exercise of placing before our eyes our friends and the ways in which they are immortal, we may consider other possibly immortal goods–for instance, the Doctrines of true philosophy, or the Four Sisters mentioned in PD 5. Reasons to include them among the “immortal goods” have been sufficiently expounded in our reasonings and video about PD 5. They are important points of reference in our ethics, and in our expectations of each other and our social contract–and since the LM mentions that these “immortal goods” must be a feature of our surroundings, and it’s hard to imagine a godlike lifestyle without them, The Four Sisters (Pleasure, Nobility, Justice, Prudence) must also be “athanatoi agathoi“.

If we apply this criterion of “memorability” to the immortal goods, we must also recognize that practices that produce blissful or pleasant states (even if not anchored in a past memory) can also be counted among the immortal goods if they have a similar transcendental quality as our remembered pleasures. I would argue that anything that helps us to feel fresh pleasures without fail (whether it is yoga, exercise, laughter practice, etc.) can also be counted among our immortal goods for a long as the enjoyment persists.

If Wisdom Dies …

We must also consider why wisdom (sophia) is mortal–but not phronesis (“practical wisdom”)–while friendship is immortal, as per VS 78. If Wisdom dies, if she’s not immortal, this is an interesting philosophical statement.

It may be that the statement that Wisdom is mortal is meant to diminish our sense of pride in our intellectual achievement, and to cure the pedantry that is often part of how other schools practice philosophy.

Might it also be that knowledge (or wisdom) does not produce the memorable feeling of pleasure that friends and salient experiences produce? Maybe this refers to cognitive decay: our brain’s abilities decay as we age, so that wisdom is seen to fade. If the first is the case, then the “memorable” criterion for things that are “immortal goods”, or at least “worthy of immortality”, is accurate.

Furthermore, we must consider Lucretius’ passage that calls the Doctrines of Epicurus “golden, and worthy of immortal life” in light of these considerations. It seems like he, at least, considered the words of true philosophy (epitomized in Epicurus’ Doctrines) to be among the immortal goods, incarnations or instances of phronesis (practical wisdom).

Memorable Experiences and our Hedonic Regimen

If memorable experiences are what characterizes immortal goods, then we may survey what memorable experiences we carry in our souls, so as to cultivate them. If it is true friends, then we may seek them out. If it’s the virtues mentioned in PD 5, then we may seek to find orientation in our choices and avoidances so as to ensure the presence of those virtues in our environment.

What goods do we consider worthy of immortality? How do we gain a godlike appearance, or create a godlike lifestyle and godlike surroundings? And, finally, how can we plan our life so as to live surrounded by immortal goods? These are some of the questions that may help us to gain clarity concerning the “athanatoi agathoi“. Of course, these considerations are meant to bear on our choices and rejections, so that we may swerve in the direction of these immortal goods.

Epicurean Philosophers by Nathan H. Bartman

EPICUREAN PHILOSOPHERS
Epicurean History by Nathan H. Bartman (2022)

[T]here are plenty of witnesses of the unsurpassable kindness of [Epicurus] to everybody; both his own country which honored him with brazen statues, and his friends who were so numerous that they could not be contained in whole cities; and all his acquaintances who were bound to him by nothing but the charms of his doctrine […] Also, the perpetual succession of his school, which, when every other school decayed, continued without any falling off, and produced a countless number of philosophers, succeeding one another without any interruption. (Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, Book X)

387 BCE: Plato founds his Academy.
384 BCE: Aristotle is born in the Central Macedonian city of Stagira.
348 BCE: Plato dies at the age of 80 due to natural causes.
341 BCE: Epicurus is born on the Island of Samos.
338 BCE: Aristotle begins three years of teaching 13-year-old Alexander III of Macedon.
334 BCE: Aristotle founds his Lyceum at the age of 50.
327 BCE: A 14-year-old Epicurus is tutored by a Platonist named Pamphilus
326 BCE: Alexander III of Macedon invades India; Pyrrho follows. As a result …
325 BCE: Pyrrho adopts the Indian school of Ajñāna and develops Skepticism
323 BCE: An 18-year-old Epicurus serves two years of Athenian conscription
322 BCE: Aristotle dies at the age of 62 due to natural causes.
321 BCE: A 20-year-old Epicurus moves with family to Colophon and studies under the Peripatetic Praxiphanes; he later studies under Nausiphanes of Teos, a Democritean pupil of Pyrrho whom he criticizes in his works
316 BCE: A 25-year-old Epicurus observes Halley’s Comet with Nausiphanes
311 BCE: A 30-year-old Epicurus begins teaching in Mytilene on the island of Lesbos
310 BCE: A 31-year-old Epicurus relocates Northward to Lampsacus
309 BCE: A 32-year-old Epicurus directly witnesses a Total Solar Eclipse
306 BCE: A 35-year-old Epicurus moves to Athens and establishes the Garden

HEGEMON HΓEMΩN – /hɛːɡe.’mɔːn/ – Leader” of the Epicurean Community

Hegemon: EPICURUS* of SAMOS (c. 11 January 341 – 270/69 BCE) the founder

KATHEGEMONES KAΘHΓEMΩNHΣ – /ka.tʰɛːɡe.’mɔːniːz/ – “Guides”

Kathegemon: POLYAENUS* of LAMPSACUS (c. 345 – 286 BCE)
Kathegemon: METRODORUS* of LAMPSACUS (c. 331/0 – 278/7 BCE)
Kathegemon: HERMARCHUS* of MYTILENE (c. 325 – 250 BCE)

*The founder and his three allies are called HOI ANDRES OI ANΔPEΣ – “The Men

DIADOCHOI ΔIAΔOXOI – /diː’a.dɔːkʰoi̯/ – “Succession” of Epicurean Scholarchs

Scholarch (1st): HERMARCHUS* (c. 325 – 250 BCE) Scholarch from 270 to 250 BCE
Scholarch (2nd): POLYSTRATUS (c. 300 – 219/8 BCE) from 250 to 219/8 BCE

NOTE: Scholarchs after Polystratus will NOT have personally known Epicurus.

Scholarch (3rd): DIONYSIUS of LAMPTRAI (c. 280 – 205 BCE) from 219/8 to 205 BCE
Scholarch (4th): BASILIDES of TYRUS (c. 245 – 175 BCE) from 205 to 175 BCE
Scholarch (5th): PROTARCHUS of BARGHILIA (c. 225 – 150 BCE) from 175 to 150 BCE
Scholarch (6th): APOLLODORUS of ATHENS (c. 200 – 125 BCE) from 147 to 125 BCE
Scholarch (7th): ZENO of SIDON (c. 166 – 75 BCE) Scholarch from 125 to 75 BCE
Scholarch (8th): PHAEDRUS (c. 138 – 70/69 BCE) Scholarch from 75 to 70/69 BCE
Scholarch (9th): PATRO (c. 100 – 25 BCE) Scholarch from 70/69 to 51 BCE

In A.D. 121 the then incumbent, Popillius Theotimus, appealed to Plotina, widow of the emperor Trajan and a devoted adherent, to intercede with Hadrian for relief from a requirement that the head should be a Roman citizen, which had resulted in unfortunate choices. The petition was granted and acknowledged with all the gratitude that was proper to the sect. (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 332)

Scholarch (16ish): POPILLIUS THEOTIMUS (early 2nd-century CE)
Scholarch (17ish): HELIODORUS (2nd-century CE) Hadrian writes him.

Later in the century it is on record that the school became a beneficiary of the bounty of Marcus Aurelius [161-180 CE], who bestowed a stipend of 10,000 drachmas per annum upon the heads of all the recognized schools” (Epicurus and His Philosophy 332)

KATHEGETES KAΘHΓHTEΣ – /ka.tʰɛːgɛː’tʰiːz/ – “Down from the Guides” or Teachers

Kathegete: ARISTOBULUS of SAMOS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) brother of Epicurus
Kathegete: CHAERDEMUS of SAMOS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) brother of Epicurus
Kathegete: NEOCLES of SAMOS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) another brother of Epicurus

GNORIMOI ΓNΩPIMOI /gnɔːriː’moi̯/ “Known Familiars” or Disciples

APELLES (4th – 3rd-century BCE) the recipient of one of Epicurus’ many epistles
APOLLODORUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) the brother of Leonteus
BATIS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) Idomeneus wife and Metrodorus‘ sister
BOIDION (4th – 3rd-century BCE) calf-eyes” hetaera who studied at the Garden
CALLISTRATUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
CARNEISCUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) dedicated a book to Philainis
COLOTES of LAMPSACUS (c. 320 – 268 BCE) a popular Greek writer known for satire
CRONIUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) a former student of Eudoxus
CTESSIPUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) attested in a letter fragment written by Epicurus
DEMELATA (4th – 3rd-century BCE) attested by Philodemus
DEMETRIA (4th – 3rd-century BCE) a companion to Hermarchus
EROTION (4th – 3rd-century BCE) lovely” hetaera who studied at the Garden
EUDEMUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) mentioned in a letter written by Epicurus
HEDEIA (3rd-century BCE) delectable” companion to Polyaenus
HIPPOCLIDES of LAMPSACUS (c. 300 – 219/8 BCE) born on the same day as Polystratus
IDOMENEUS of LAMPSACUS (c. 310 – 270 BCE) the main financier of the Garden
LEONTEUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) the husband of Themista
LEONTION (4th – 3rd-century BCE) lioness“, a respected writer and courtesan
LYCOPHRON (4th – 3rd-century BCE) a correspondent of Leonteus of Lampsacus
MAMMARION (3rd-century BCE) tits“, a possible lover to Leonteus
MENESTRATUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) pupil of Metrodorus
MENOECEUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCEof EpicurusLetter to Menoeceus
MENTORIDES of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) the eldest brother of Metrodorus
MYS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) mouse” a male slave who managed publishing
NICANOR (4th – 3rd-century BCE) student of Epicurus attested by Diogenes Laërtius
NIKIDION (4th – 3rd-century BCE)  victress” possible lover to Idomeneus
PHILAINIS (4th – 3rd-century BCEattested by Philodemus
PHILISTAS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) inspired Carneiscus to write
PYTHOCLES of LAMPSACUS (c. 324 — 3rd-century BCE) of Epicurus’ Letter to Pythocles
THEMISTA of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) wife of Leonteus
THEOPHILIA (4th – 3rd-century BCE) attested by 1st-century Roman poet Martial

HELLENIC PHILOIΦIΛΩI – /’pʰi.loi̯/ Friends” or Associates

ANAXARCHUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
ARCHEPHON (4th – 3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
CHARMIDES (4th – 3rd-century BCE) a friend of Arcesilaus the Academic Skeptic
DOSITHEUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) the father of Hegesianax
ERASISTRATUS of CHIOS (c. 304 – 250 BCE) of the Alexandrian school of medicine
ZOPYRUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
ALEXANDRIA the ATOMIST (3rd-century BCE) associated with Alexandria
ANTIDORUS THE EPICUREAN (3rd-century BCE) who wrote a work against Heraclides
APOLLONIDES (3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
APOLLODORUS the EPICUREAN (3rd-century BCE) a pupil of Polystratus
ARTEMON of LAODICEA (3rd-century BCE) one of several teachers of Philonides
AUTODORUS the EPICUREAN (3rd-century BCE) criticizes Heraclides
CINEAS the EPICUREAN (3rd-century BCE) advised King Pyrrhus of Epirus (Plutarch)
DIODORUS (3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
DIOTIMUS OF SEMACHIDES (3rd-century BCE) a pupil of Polystratus
EUGATHES (3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
EUPHRONIUS (3rd-century BCE) ridiculed by Plutarch
HEGESIANAX (3rd-century BCE) son of Dositheus
HERMOCRATES (3rd-century BCE) who proposed natural explanation for prayer
PYRSON (3rd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
THEOPHEIDES (3rd-century BCE) a friend of Hermarchus
ANTIPHANES (3rd – 2nd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
ANTIOCHUS IV EPIPHANES (c. 3rd-century – 164 BCE) king and student to Philonides
ARISTONYMUS (3rd – 2nd-century BCE) a friend of Dionysius
DIOGENES of SELEUCIA (c. 3rd-century – 146 BCE) was put to death by Antiochus VI
HELIODORUS OF ANTIOCH (3rd – 2nd-century BCE) an official of Seleucus IV
ALCAEUS (2nd-century BCE) Sent and expelled from Rome with Philiscus in 154 BCE
CEPHISOPHON (2nd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
DAMOPHANES (2nd-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
DEMETRIUS I SOTER (c. 185 – 150 BCE) a student to Philonides
EUCRATIDES of RHODES (2nd-century BCE) was known only by his gravestone
HERACLITUS of RHODIAPOLIS (2nd-century BCE) an Athenian physician
IOLAUS OF BITHYNIA (2nd-century BCE) a physician associated with Epicureanism
NICASICRATES of RHODES (2nd-century BCE) called a “dissident” by Philodemus
PHILISCUS (2nd-century BCE) Sent and expelled from Rome with Alcaeus in 154 BCE
PHILONIDES of LAODICEA (c. 200 – 130 BCE) Founded school in Antioch
THESPIS the EPICUREAN (2nd-century BCE) student of Basilides; taught Philodemus
TIMASAGORAS of RHODES (2nd-century BCE) called a “dissident” by Philodemus
ATHENAEUS (2nd – 1st-century BCE) a pupil of Polyaenus of Lampsacus
ATHENAGORAS (2nd – 1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
ASCLEPIADES of BITHYNIA (124 – 40 BCE) Physician with atomic drug theory
IRENAEUS OF MILETUS (2nd – 1st-century BCE) a pupil of Demetrius Lacon
PHILODEMUS of GADARA (c. 110 – 30 BCE) manuscripts preserved in Herculaneum
ANTIGENES (1st-century BCE) friend of Philodemus
ANTIPATER (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
APOLLOPHANES of PERGAMUM (1st-century BCE) sent to Rome to teach
BACCHUS (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
BROMIUS (1st-century BCE) peer to Philodemus; Zeno of Sidon’s pupil
DEMETRIUS LACON (1st-century BCE) Founded Milesian school; taught Philodemus
DIOGENES of TARSUS (1st-century BCE) travels with Plutiades of Tarsus
EGNATIUS (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
LYSIAS of TARSUS (1st-century BCE) Tyrant of Tarsus who butchered the wealthy
ORION the EPICUREAN (1st-century BCE) Epicurean “notable” per Laërtius
PLATO OF SARDIS (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
PLUTIADES of TARSUS (1st-century BCE) travels with Diogenes of Tarsus
PTOLEMEUS the BLACK of ALEXANDRIA (1st-century BCE) “notable” per Laërtius
PTOLEMEUS the WHITE of ALEXANDRIA (1st-century BCE) “notable” per Laërtius
TIMAGORAS (1st-century BCE) attested by Cicero
ARTEMIDORUS OF PARIUM (1st-century BCE/CE) fragmentary attestation
ATHENODORUS (1st-century CE) fragmentary attestation
ATHENODORUS OF ATHENS (1st-century CE) fragmentary attestation
AMYNIAS of SAMOS (1st-century CE) only known due to a stone inscription
BOETHUS OF SIDON (1st-century CE) an acquaintance of Plutarch
DIONYSIUS OF RHODES (1st-century CE) a friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda
MENNEAS (1st-century CE) fragmentary attestation
POLLIUS FELIX (1st-century CE) a patron of the poet Statius
THEODORIDAS OF LINDUS (1st-century CE) a friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda
XENOCLES OF DELPHI (1st-century CE) an acquaintance of Plutarch
XENOCRITOS (1st-century CE) known only from a stone inscription
EPICURIUS (1st – 2nd-century CE) a philosopher attested by Plutarch
CELSUS [1] the EPICUREAN (2nd-century CE) a friend of Lucian of Samosata
CELSUS [2] the EPICUREAN (2nd-century CE) a Greek opponent to the Christian church
DIOCLES the EPICUREAN (2nd-century CE) a Greek opponent to the Christian church
DIOGENES of OENOANDA (2nd-century CE) posted teachings on a 205-ft. wall
DIOGENIANUS (2nd-century CE) who wrote a polemic against Chrysippus
HERACLITUS of RHODIAPOLIS (2nd-century CE) known from a stone inscription
LUCIAN OF SAMOSATA (c. 125 – 180 CE) a Syrian satirist
NICERATUS of RHODES (2nd-century CE) a close friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda
PHILIDAS HERACLEONOS of DIDYMA (2nd-century CE) known from a stone inscription
ZENOCRATES THE EPICUREAN (2nd – 3rd-century CE) a hedonist
EXUPERANTIA (3rd – 4th-century CE) the wife of Heraclamon Leonides
HERACLAMON LEONIDES (3rd – 4th-century CE) the husband of Exuperantia

ROMAN AMICI AMICI – /a’miːkiː / Friends” or “Associates”

ANTONIUS (2nd-century BCE) Exchanged views with Galen on medical matters.
GAIUS AMAFINIUS (late 2nd-century BCE) among the first Epicureans to write in Latin
RABIRIUS (late 2nd-century BCE) among the first Epicureans to write in Latin
TITUS ALBUCIUS (late 2nd-century BCE) studied in Athens; passed teachings to Rome
AULUS TORQUATUS (2nd – 1st-century BCE) a relative of L. Manlius
CATIUS INSUBER (c. 2nd-century – 45 BCE) popular Celtic author from Northern Italy
LUCIUS CORNELIUS SISENNA (2nd – 1st-century BCE) a historian
LUCIUS MANLIUS TORQUATUS (2nd-century – 46 BCE) a friend of Cicero
NERO THE EPICUREAN (2nd – 1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
TITUS POMPONIUS ATTICUS (110 – 32 BCE) Close friend of Cicero; wisely apolitical
ANTHIS (1st-century BCE) a freedwoman of Calpurnia Caesaris
AURELIUS OPILIUS (1st-century BCE) Freedman who retired to Mytilene
DION (1st-century BCE) A philosopher for whom Cicero had no regard
LUCIUS AUFIDIUS BASSUS (1st-century BCE) Used philosophy to deal with illness
LUCIUS CORNELIUS BALBUS (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
LUCIUS LUCCESIUS (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
LUCIUS PAPIRIUS PAETUS (1st-century BCE) good friends with Cicero
LUCIUS SAUFEIUS (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero and Atticus; seemingly apolitical
LUCIUS VARIUS RUFUS (1st-century BCE) Roman poet and associate of Virgil
MARCUS FADIUS GALLUS (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
MARCUS POMPILIUS ANDRONICUS (1st-century BCE) correspondent with Cicero
MARCUS VALERIUS MESSALLA CORVINUS (1st-century BCE) a friend of Horace
MARIUS the EPICUREAN (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero and subject of a text
MATIUS the EPICUREAN (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
PLAUTIUS TUCCA (1st-century BCE) Roman poet and associate of Virgil
PUBLIUS CORNELIUS DOLABELLA (1st-century BCE) Senate declared him an “enemy”
PUBLIUS VOLUMNIUS ETRAPELUS (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
SIRO (1st-century BCE) Pupil of Zeno; taught Virgil; founded the school in Naples
STATILIUS the EPICUREAN (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
TREBIANUS (1st-century BCE) fragmentary attestation
VELLEIUS the EPICUREAN (1st-century BCE) a friend of Cicero
LUCIUS CALPURNIUS PISO CAESONINUS (c. 100 – 43 BCE) friend of Cicero
TITUS LUCRETIUS CARUS (99 – 55 BCE) writes De Rerum Natura
GAIUS VIBIUS PANSA CAETRONIANUS (c. 90s – 43 BCE) Friend of Cicero
AULUS HIRTIUS (c. 90 – 43 BCE) a friend of Cicero and former lobbyist against Caesar
GAIUS CASSIUS LONGINUS (86 – 42 BCE) a friend of Cicero
CAIUS TREBATIUS TESTA (84 BCE – 4 CE) a friend of Cicero
CALPURNIA CAESARIS (c. 75 BCE – 00s BCE) Daughter of Piso
PUBLIUS VIRGILIUS MARO (70 – 19 BCE) student of Siro at the Garden of Naples
GAIUS CILNIUS MAECENAS (70 – 8 BCE) political advisor to Octavian/Augustus
QUINTUS HORACE HORATIUS FLACCUS (65 – 8 BCE) Coined carpe diem or “seize the day!
CAIUS STALLIUS HAURANUS (1st-century BCE – 1st-century CE) a student in Naples
LUCIUS CALPURNIUS PISO PONTIFEX (48 BCE – 32 CE) the son of Piso Caesoninus
PUBLIUS QUINTILIUS VARUS (46 BCE – 9 CE) a general and fellow-student of Virgil
ALEXANDER the EPICUREAN (1st-century CE) who was “fond of learning”
DIODORUS the EPICUREAN (1st-century CE) who allegedly committed suicide
GAIUS PETRONIUS ARBITER (c. 27 – 66 CE) who allegedly committed suicide
MARCUS GAVIUS APICIUS (1st-century CE) a gourmet during Tiberius’ reign
NOMENTANUS (1st-century CE) a Roman Epicurean during Tiberius’ reign
PUBLIUS MANLIUS VOPISCUS (1st-century CE) a patron of the poet Statius
CAIUS ARTORIUS CELER (1st – 2nd-century CE) a philosopher from North Africa
EMPRESS POMPEIA PLOTINA CLAUDIA PHOEBE PISO (c. 68 – 121/2 CE) Trajan‘s widow
MAXIMUS THE EPICUREAN (1st – 2nd-century CE) fragmentary attestation
AURELIUS BELIUS PHILIPPUS (2nd-century CE) Head of Apamean school
DAMIS THE EPICUREAN (2nd-century CE) whose historical personage is poorly attested
PUDENTIANUS (2nd-century CE) Galen wrote a lost work to him
TIBERIUS CLAUDIUS LEPIDUS (2nd-century CE) Founded school in Amastris
EMPEROR LUCIUS SEPTIMIUS SEVERUS (145 – 211 CE) Emperor from 193 to 211
ZENOBIUS (2nd – 3rd-century CE) the target of a book by Alexander of Aphrodisias
PALLADAS of ALEXANDRIA (4th-century CE) the “last known ancient Epicurean”

We have seen that at the beginning of the third century AD, some five centuries after the death of its founder, Epicureanism was still alive both in major centres and in remoter parts of the Graeco-Roman world. It is generally held, however, that its demise lay not far off, that by the middle of the fourth century it would have become a virtually forgotten creed, overwhelmed, along with Stoicism, by the spread of Christianity, fully justifying St. Augustine’s boast that ‘its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them‘. (Jones, Epicurean Tradition 94)

MEDIEVAL EPICUREANS:

FREDERICK II, HOLY ROMAN EMPEROR (1194 – 1250) who burns in Dante’s Inferno
FARINATA DEGLI UBERTI (1212 – 1264) a Florentine who burns in Dante’s Inferno
CAVALCANTE DE’ CAVALCANTI (c. 1230 – 1280) who burns in Dante’s Inferno
MANFRED, KING OF SICILY (1232 – 1266) the son of Frederick II
GUIDO CAVALCANTI (c. 1250 – 1300) best friend of Dante and son of Cavalcante

MODERN EPICUREANS AND NEO-EPICUREANS:

LORENZO VALLA (1406 – 1457) wrote On Pleasure and sympathized with Epicurus
ERASMUS OF ROTTERDAM (1466 – 1536) a Dutch philosopher and Humanist
LUDOVICO ARIOSTO (1474 – 1533) a poet who employed Epicurean themes
GIOVANNI DI LORENZO DE’ MEDICI, POPE LEO X (1475 – 1521) a Humanist
FRANCESCO GUICCIARDINI (1483 – 1540) of the Italian Renaissance
MICHEL EYQUEM DE MONTAIGNE (1533 – 1592) of the French Renaissance
ELIO DIODATAI (1576 – 1661) a Genevan jurist and supporter of Galileo
FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER (1588 – 1672) a writer and friend of Moliére
ISAAC BEECKMAN (1588 – 1637) a Dutch philosopher who advised Gassendi
TH
ÉOPHILE DE VIAU (1590 – 1626) banished from France on charges of immorality
PIERRE GASSENDI (1592 – 1655) tried to reconcile Epicureanism with Christianity
JACQUES VALLÉE, SIEUR DES BARREAUX (1599 – 1673) a French poet
FRANÇOIS LUILLIER (1600 – 1651) known as a practicing Epicurean
GABRIEL NAUDÉ (1600 – 1653) a French librarian and friend of Gassendi
GUILLES DE LAUNAY (c. 1600– 1675) wrote that Epicurus was the ideal natural philosopher
GUI PATIN (1601 – 1672) a French doctor and great friend of Gabriel Naudé
EMMANUEL MAIGNAN (1601 – 1676) a French physicist and Christian Epicurean
JEAN FRANÇOIS SARASIN (1611 – 1654) a French writer and Epicurean devotee
MARION DE LORME (1613 – 1650) a famous French courtesan
CHARLES DE SAINT-ÉVREMOND (1613 – 1703) a follower of Gassendi
FRANÇOIS VI, DUC DE LA ROCHEFOUCAULD (1613 – 1680) a French author
ANTOINE MENJOT (c. 1615 – 1696) a French doctor and follower of Gassendi
WALTER CHARLETON (1619 – 1707) a main transmitter of Epicureanism to England
SAVINIEN DE CYRANO DE BERGERAC (1619 – 1655) a French novelist and playwright
FRANÇOIS BERNIER (1620 – 1688) a French physician and follower of Gassendi
NINON DE L’ENCLOS (1620 – 1705) an author who left her inheritance for 9-year-old Voltaire
THOMAS WILLIS (1621 – 1675) an English doctor and contemporary of Charleton
JEAN DE LA FONTAINE (1621 – 1695) a widely-read French poet and fabulist
MARGARET CAVENDISH, DUCHESS (1623 – 1673) an atomist but not a classical Epicurean
MADAME MARIE DE RABUTIN-CHANTAL, MARQUISE DE SÉVIGNÉ (1626 – 1696)
SIR WILLIAM TEMPLE, 1st BARONET (1628 – 1699) an essayist and friend of Wilmot
ANTOINETTE DESHOULIÈRES (1634 – 1655) a French, epicurean poet
GUILLAUME AMFRYE DE CHAULIEU (1639 – 1720) a convinced Epicurean poet
APHRA BEHN (1640 – 1689) an English playwright, poet, writer, and libertine translator
GUILLAUME LAMY (1644 – 1683) a French physician who taught La Mettrie
CHARLES AUGUSTE DE LA FARE (1644 – 1712) a French poet and friend of Chaulieu
JACQUES PARRAIN DES COUTURES (1645 – 1702) who wrote La Morale d’Epicure
JOHN WILMOT, 2nd EARL of ROCHESTER (1647 – 1680) a satirist; friend of Temple
JEAN DE LA CHAPELLE (1651 – 1723) the “father of French epicurean poetry.”
FRANÇOIS COURTIN (1659 – 1739) abbot of Mont-Saint-Quentin by age nineteen
WILLIAM CONGREVE (1670 – 1729) an English playwright of the Restoration Period
BERNARD MANDEVILLE (1670 – 1733) an Anglo-Dutch economist and satirist
CELESTINO GALIANI (1681 – 1753) an Archbishop and “Christian Epicurean”
JULIEN OFFRAY DE LA METTRIE (1709 – 1751) grounded mental processes in the body
FREDERICK II of PRUSSIA (1712 – 1786) also known as “Frederick The Great”
DENIS DIDEROT (1713 – 1784) a French author, social critic, and religious skeptic
CLAUDE ADRIEN HELVÉTIUS (1715 – 1771) a French utilitarian philosopher
PAUL-HENRI THIRY, BARON D’HOLBACH (1723 – 1789) an atheist
THOMAS JEFFERSON (1743 – 1826) the third President of the United States of America
JEREMY BENTHAM (1748 – 1832) an English philosopher and founder Utilitarianism
RICHARD PAYNE KNIGHT (1751 – 1824) an English classical scholar and collector
PIERRE JEAN GEORGES CABANIS (1757 – 1808) a French physiologist and materialist
WILLIAM SHORT (17591849) an ambassador and friend of Thomas Jefferson
WALTER SAVAGE LANDOR (1775 – 1864) an English writer, poet, and activist
CHARLES GREVILLE (1794 – 1865) an English diarist and amateur cricket player
FRANCIS WRIGHT (1795 – 1852) a Scottish-American writer, feminist, and abolitionist
WALT WHITMAN (1819 – 1892) an American poet whose father attended Wright’s lectures
WILLIAM WALLACE (1844 – 1897) a Scottish philosopher inspired by Epicurus
ROBERT LOUIS STEVENSON (1850 – 1894) an American author (see: Treasure Island)
JEAN-MARIE GUYAU
(1854 – 1888) a French author and anarchist who died at the age of 33
HENRY DWIGHT SEDGWICK (1861 – 1957) wrote Memoirs of an Epicurean
CHARLES LEOPOLD MAYER (1881 – 1971) a French biochemist and Liberal
JUN TSUJI (1884 – 1944) a Japanese dadaist, absurdist, poet, essayist and playwright
H. P. LOVECRAFT (1890 – 1927) Cosmicism was inspired by Epicureanism
YAAKOV MALKIN (1926-2019) Rabbi of the Secular Humanist Jewish denomination
JOSÉ MUJICA (1935 – PRESENT) a farmer and 40th President of Uruguay (2010-15)

CHRISTOPHER HITCHENS (1949 – 2011) a writer, polemicist and religious critic
HARIS DIMITRIADIS (1952 – PRESENT) writer and promoter of Epicurean philosophy
CASSIUS AMICUS (1958 – PRESENT) a writer and proprietor of New Epicurean 
HIRAM CRESPO (1975 – PRESENT) a writer and founder of SocietyOfEpicurus.com
NATHAN H. BARTMAN (1988 – PRESENT) author of this historical investigation.

FORMER EPICUREANS:

TIMOCRATES of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) brother of Metrodorus
HERODOTUS of LAMPSACUS (4th – 3rd-century BCE) a friend of Timocrates
METRODORUS of STRATONECIUS (2nd-century BCEconverted to Academic Skepticism
CICERO (106 BCE – 43 BCE) a student of Phaedrus and fierce critic of Epicureanism
SAUL of TARSUS (c. 5 – 65 CE) who is better known as St. Paul the Apostle

EPICUREAN COMMUNITIES:

[Epicurus] philosophy rode this tide. It had reached Alexandria even before his arrival in Athens. By the second century it was flourishing in Antioch and Tarsus, had invaded Judaea, and was known in Babylon. Word of it had reached Rome while Epicurus was still living, and in the last century B.C. it swept over Italy. […] Both Thessalonica and Corinth must have been strongholds of Epicureanism.” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 29, 338)

After the third century BCE there were Epicurean centres in Asia Minor, Syria, and Egypt: adherents, identified from their cities, came from Tyre, Sidon, Tarsus, and Alexandria. Epicureanism also expanded west. […] The existence of communities in the Naples region is attested by both Horace and Vergil. […] Epicureanism can be attested in a board variety of locations: Herculanem, Sorrento, Rhodes, Cos,Pergamon, Oenoanda (the Lycus valley), Apameia (Syria), Rhodiapolis, and Amastris (Bithynia). Locations like Athens and Oxyrhynchus provide evidence for the preservation fo Epicurean writing, as well as Herculaneum. […] Asia Minor (notably Ephesus, Alexandria, and Syria are all suggested as prime candidates for its location. (King, Epicureanism and the Gospel of John: A Study of Their Comparability 11-13)

It will be worth our while to observe how admirably Epicureanism was equipped for the penetration for Asia. As mentioned already, the branch school at Lampsacus was strategically situated for dissemination of the creed along the coast of the Black Sea. On the west coast of Asia there was another school at Mytilene […] Still further to the south was the original school at Colophon, close to Ephesus. […] The gateway to Asia, however, had been open to the cred of Epicurus for three centuries before Paul’s time and Tarsus was a center of Epicureanism. […] Epicureanism was the court philosophy of Antioch during the reigns of at least two kings of Syria, Antiochus Epiphanes and Demetrius Soter. (King, Epicureanism and the Gospel of John: A Study on Their Comparability 62)

In it he attests the widespread Epicurean communities of Athens, and Chalcis and Thebes in Boeotia. […] We meet Epicureans not just in Athens, where they were amongst Paul’s audiences, but we also come across Epicurean communities in the West, in Herculaneum or Sorrento, in the East, on Rhodes and Cos, in Pergamon, Lycian Oinoanda, Syrian Apameia, in remote southern Lycian Rhodiapolis or in Amastris in Bithynia on the Black Sea. (The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism 20, 48)

School at LAMPSACUS (modern Northwestern Turkey) Founded by Epicurus
The GARDEN (O KHΠOΣ) of ATHENS (Central Greece) Founded by Epicurus
Community in CORINTH (Peloponnese peninsula, Greece)
Community in CHALCIS (Euboea island, Greece)
Community in THEBES (Boeotia, Central Greece)
Community in THESSALONIKI (Macedonia region, Greece)
Community in KOS (Southeastern island of Greece)
School at RHODES (Southeastern island of Greece)
School at AMASTRIS (Northern Turkey) Founded by Tiberius Claudius Lepidus
Community in TARSUS (Northwest Turkey)
Community in PERGAMON (Western Turkey)
Community in COLOPHON (Western Turkey)
Community in EPHESUS (Southwestern Turkey)
School at MILETUS (Southwestern Turkey) Founded by Demetrius Laco
Community in OINOANDA (Southwestern Turkey) Supported by Diogenes
Community in RHODIAPOLIS (Southwestern Turkey)
School at ANTIOCH (South-central Turkey) Founded by Philonides
School at APAMEIA (Western Syria) Lead by Aurelius Belius Philippus
Community at SIDON (Lebanon)
Community at TYRE (Lebanon)
Community in ALEXANDRIA (City of Alexander III of Macedon in Egypt)
Community in OXYRHYNCHUS (Southern Egypt)
School at NAPLES (Southwestern Italy) Founded by Siro
Community in HERCULANEUM (Southwestern Italy) Lead by Philodemus
Community in ROME (Western Italy) Inspired by Albucius

Greek Philoi:

Epicurus, son of Neocles and Chaerestrate, was an Athenian […] he took up philosophy at the age of fourteen. […] Epicurus was joined in his philosophical pursuits, at his urging, by his three brothers—Neocles, Chaeredemus, and Aristobulus—as Philodemus the Epicurean [110 BCE – 30 BCE] says in the tenth book of his collection On Philosophers […] (Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 492-493.)

Timocrates, the brother of Metrodorus, who studied with Epicurus and then left his school, says […] that other courtesans consorted both with [Epicurus] and with Metrodorus, including Mammarion, Hedia, Erotion, and Nicidion (Ibid. 494-495.)

[Timocrates] withdrew in anger and returned home to take service under Lysimachus in Lampsacus [a ruler to whom Epicurus owed money]. There he joined up with the other deserter Herodotus, whose feelings may have been similarly hurt, and began a campaign of pamphleteering with a view of stirring up trouble for Epicurus among the Athenians […] Two desertions are on record from this early group of adherents, an occurrence notoriously rare in the camp of Epicurus. One was that of Timocrates, the unpredictable brother of the capable Metrodorus […] The other deserter was Herodotus, who made common cause with the spiteful Timocrates and discovered specious grounds for impugning the genuineness of the loyalty of Epicurus to Athens” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 54, 82-83).

Metrodorus tells us how even Timocrates [harmed] the eldest of his brother Mentorides.” (Philodemus, On Angercol. XII.7-8)

“ … Metrodorus of Stratoniceus, defected to Carneades [the head of the skeptical Platonist Academy], perhaps because he found Epicurus’ incomparable goodness oppressive ….” (Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 497)

There also appears to have been both slaves and women in Epicurus’s schools. Gilles Ménage lists three female Epicureans: Themisto, Leontium, and Theophilia.” (Allen, The Adoption of Aristotelian and Platonic Concepts 133)

The oversight of these [publishing concerns] would undoubtedly have fallen to the talented slave whose name was Mys. […] He was rewarded by freedom at the master’s death, and tradition reports him as a philosopher in his own right” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 95).

The hetairai Boidion, Leontion, Hedeia, Nikidion, Mammarion, Demelata, Erotion, and Philainis were connected with the school. Metrodorus’ sister Batis married Idomeneus […] Leonteus married Themista […] We know that Metrodorus and Polyainos were married and had children….” (Frischer, The Sculpted World, Epicureanism and Philosophical Recruitment in Ancient Greece 62)

Epicurus had many students, and among the most distinguished was Metrodorus of Lampsacus […] Such was his character that he gave his sister Batis in marriage to Idomeneus, and took the courtesan Leontion of Athens as his concubine. […] Epicurus also had as a student […] Timocrates, Metrodorus‘ shiftless brother.” (Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 501)

Preserved in the collection at Herculaneum is a fragment of an essay by one Carneiscus, a contemporary of Epicurus, that discusses the proper attitude toward the death of a friend. The work derives its title from Carneiscus‘ fellow-Epicurean Philistas (appropriately named), who manifests the right outlook and demeanor.” (Konstan, Friendship in the Classical World 109)

Among the Herculaneum remains there is a letter of Epicurus to a little child, who may possibly be this daughter of Metrodorus. The letter runs thus: ‘We came to Lampsacus, Pythocles, Hermarchus, Ctesippus, and myself, and we are quit well. We found there Themista and our other friends, and they are quite well.” (Courtney, Studies in Philosophy: Ancient and Modern 32)

Epicurus promised Menoeceus that if we develop a firm identity and conviction in our naturalist faith, we would live as gods among mortals.” (Crespo, Tending the Epicurean Garden)

‘Let them also take care of Nicanor, as I [Epicurus] have always done, so that no members of the school who have been helpful to me in private life and shown me every kindness and chosen to grow old with me in philosophy may lack the necessities, so far as my means allow.” (Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 500)

There was also Polyaenus of Lampsacus […] and Epicurus‘ successor, Hermarchus […] There is also Leonteus of Lampsacus and his wife, Themista, with whom Epicurus corresponded; and Colotes and Idomeneus, both from Lampsacus. All of these were well-regarded, as was Polystratus, who succeeded Hermarchus. (Polystratus was succeeded by Dionysius, and Dionysius by Basilides.) Apollodorus, the ‘tyrant of the Garden,’ was also distinguished […] and the two Ptolemies from Alexandria: the Black and the White; and Zeno of Sidon, a student of Apollodorus, a prolific writer, and Demetrius, who was called the Laconian, and Diogenes of Tarsus who compiled The Selected Letters; and Orion and others whom the genuine Epicureans call ‘sophists.’” (Ibid. 502.)

“ … particularly influential contemporary of Zeno in the Garden, who, however, did not become school head, wasDemetrius of Laconia who also set up school at or near Miletus” (The Cambridge Companion To Epicureanism 32-34).

Of Epicurean scholars in the city [of Alexandria] we have the names of only two, Ptolemaeus the White and Ptolemaeus the Black, which may mean that the former was Greek and the second a native” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 340).

[M]embers and followers of the Athenian Garden found themselves more than once in conflict with the very independent Epicurean community at Rhodes, each group invoking Epicurean scripture in its own support and each ready to condemn the other as unfaithful to the canonical teachings.” (Sedley, Epicurean Theories of Knowledge From Hermarchus To Lucretius and Philodemus)

Cicero’s first systemic lessons in philosophy were given him by the Epicurean Phaedrus, then at Rome because of the unsettled state of Athens. […] The pupil seems to have been converted at once to the tenets of the master. Phaedrusremained to the end of his life a friend of Cicero, who speaks warmly in praise of his teacher’s amiable disposition and refined style. […] Cicero abandoned Epicureanism, but his schoolfellow, T. Pomponius Atticus received more lasting impressions from the teaching of Phaedrus. […] Atticus and his friend became acquainted with Patro, who succeeded Phaedrus as head of the Epicurean school.” (Reid, M. Tulli Ciceronis Academica 1)

In A.D. 121 the then incumbent, Popillius Theotimus, appealed to Plotina, widow of the emperor Trajan and a devoted adherent, to intercede with Hadrian for relief from a requirement that the head should be a Roman citizen … ”(De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 332)

[Emperor Hadrian’s] letter is followed by a document which begins with the name (in the dative) Heliodorus, who, whether or not he was the new head of the school, was clearly an Epicurean.” (Birley, Hadrian: The Restless Emperor182)

I [Epicurus] call you blessed, Apelles, [3rd-century BCE] because you have set out for philosophy undefiled by any paideia.” (Athenaeus, Deipnosophists)

Furthermore, Autodorus the Epicurean [3rd-century BCE] criticizes him in a polemic against his tract Of Justice.” (Diogenes Laërtius, On the Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, Book V 92)

Antidorus: It is unclear which Antidorus Diogenes is referencing. […] Diogenes also tells us that a certainAntidorus the Epicurean [3rd-century BCE] wrote a work against Heraclides.” (Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 256)

How should we regard, for instance, the Epicurean Diogenes of Seleucia, who long enjoyed the king’s favor in spite of his offensive behavior, until he was finally executed (Ath. 5.211a-d)?” (Oxford Handbook of Epicurus and Epicureanism 303)

The talented physician Erasistratus of Antioch [3rd-century BCE] and Alexandria, an atomist, if not certainly an Epicurean, had proposed the theory that the air [atmosphere] breathed into the lungs was transformed by the heart into the vital breath, pneuma, Latin spiritus, and these words became regular designations for the immortal part of man [to Christians]. […] the brilliant physician Erasistratus, at least an atomist, if not an Epicurean” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 259).

There is also the inscription honoring the Epicurean Eucratides of Rhodes […] From Rhodiapolis comes the inscription honoring the physician and philosopher Heraclitus—if not an Epicurean at least connected with the Epicureans of Athens” (Clay, Paradosis and Survival 235)

“The fragmentary nature of the text makes it difficult to ascertain whether Euphronius is meant to be an early Epicurean or Aelian’s contemporary.” (Gordon, The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus 156)

Proclus solves a problem in the Platonic theory of prayer which had already been pointed out by the Epicurean Hermocrates [3rd-century BCE] – does one have to pray to be able to pray properly? – by using Epicurean ideas of prayer as meditation, when the good is not a result generated from outside, but consists in the act of the prayer itself and, consequently, in looking after the self.” (The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism 60)

A senatus consultum decreed the ejection of two Epicurean philosophers, Alcaeus and Philiscus. […] The texts indicate that Alcaeus and Philiscus were removed because they introduced unnatural pleasures to the young. The charge may derive from a source hostile to Epicureanism which added the motive because of the negative stereotype attached to the school, rather than from the actual wording of the senatus consultum.” (Gruen, Studies in Greek culture and Roman policy 177)

The gateway to Asia, however, had been open to the creed of Epicurus for three centuries before Paul’s time and Tarsus was a center of Epicureanism. In the second century B.C. a renegade Epicurean [Lysias of Tarsus] had made himself a tyrant of the city and ruled it for a time. In the same century a famous Epicurean philosopher named Diogeneshad flourished there; his writings on the doctrines of Epicurus were in circulation for centuries. Meanwhile, Epicureanism was the court philosophy at Antioch during the reigns of at least two kings of Syria, Antiochus Epiphanes and Demetrius Soter.” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 62)

[A]t Tarsus an Epicurean philosopher who had become the tyrant of that city, Lysias by name; who having been created by his countrymen Stephanephorus, that is to say, the priest of Heracles, did not lay down his command, but seized on the tyranny. He put on a purple tunic with a white centre, and over that he wore a very superb and costly cloak, and he put on white Lacedaemonian sandals, and assumed also a crown of golden laurel leaves. And he distributed the property of the rich among the poor, and put many to death who did not surrender their property willingly.” (Deipnosophists, Book V)

With Thespis [2nd-century BCE], another Epicurean, he played a role in an argument concerning the subject of anger, both of them [with Philonides] taking a position against Nicasicrates and Timasagoras.” (Oxford Handbook of Epicurus and Epicureanism 22)

An inference similar to the one made by Velleius can be found in a discussion by Demetrius Laco about the forms of the gods […] as well as in Zeno of Sidon’s discussion on inference from analogy as quoted by Philodemus in On Signs[…] Of greatest relevance is a section of the treatise that quotes notes from Zeno’s lectures taken by Philodemus‘ fellow student Bromius ….” (Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition 141)

Among the other philosophers from Tarsus […] are Plutiades [1st-century BCE] and Diogenes, who were among those philosophers that went round from city to city and conducted schools in an able manner.” (Strabo, Geography 14.5.15)

The first and most dogged sees Asclepiades as a medical atomist, and the corpuscular hypothesis as an adaptation of Epicurean atomism.” (Vallance, The Lost Theory of Asclepiades of Bithynia 10)

According to Seneca, an Epicurean philosopher named Diodorus who committed suicide in the mid-first century CE chose as his last words the penultimate declaration of Virgil’s Dido […] (‘I have lived, and I have run the course that fortune granted,’ Aen. 4.653). Diodorus the Epicurean is otherwise unknown, and it is difficult to appraise Seneca’s claim that Diodorus quoted Dido before slitting his own throat.” (Gordon, The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus68)

The evidences from the second century are remarkable. Parallel to the previous refutation of the Epicurean Diocles by the Peripatetic Sotion we find the Christian Origen of Caesarea refuting the Roman Epicurean Celsus […] Celsus was the attacker.” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 349)


“An Epicurean named
Xenocles, for example, weighs in on the salubriousness of fruit, as opposed to elaborate dishes (635b-c). Alexander the Epicurean is ‘accomplished and fond of learning’ […] whereas Plutarch, who is avoiding eggs because of a dream about them, drolly presents himself in that dialogue as superstitious. The mild Boethus [1st-century CE], an Epicurean and mathematician who appears in Table Talk as well as in Why the Pythia No Longer Delivers Oracles in Verse, is never pilloried, though it is possible that we should regard him as the recipient of ‘incidental polemic’” (Gordon, The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus 157)

Xenocritos […] son of Aresteas, who is listed with the title ‘Epicurean philosopher’ among the molpoi who made a votive dedication for the health of the archiereus G. Julius Apollonides, son of Gaius, on the island of Amorgos.” (Ahlholm, Philosophers in Stone: Philosophy and Self-Representation in Epigraphy of the Roman Empire 72)

Little is known of the Epicurean Diogenianus. He likely flourished in the second century AD; Eusebius preserves what is known of his works. For criticism of the pagan belief in oracles Eusebius quotes from Diogenianus‘ attack on Chrysippus’ doctrine of Fate ….” (Carriker, The Library of Eusebius of Caesarea 89)

Throughout Lucian’s work, the classic enemies of the Epicureans – the Platonists, the Stoics, the Academics, and others – are the prime targets of his biting words. But Epicurus himself is never treated with less than courtesy, and rarely if ever is the later Epicurean a target of derision. In general, Lucian refers to Epicurus in tones that can only be described as reverential …” (Amicus, Lion of Epicurus – Lucian and His Epicurean Passages 1)

The new investigations at Oenoanda initiated by Smith in 1968 have led to the discovery of two new letters from Diogenes‘ epistolary: a letter to Dionysius of Rhodes […] and a long letter Diogenes [of Oenoanda] addressed to his associates in Rhodes concerning an Epicurean by the name of Niceratus.” (Clay, Paradosis and Survival: Three Chapters in the History of Epicurean Philosophy 241)

A third case of an Epicurean priest comes from Miletos. Those who held the year-long post of prophet in charge of Apollo’s sanctuary at Didyma often ended their year by setting up an inscription documenting their role, and one of these involves Philidas, an Epicurean philosopher …” (Harland, North Coast of the Black Sea, Asia Minor)

In Alciphron’s Letters of Parasites, the philosopher guests at a birthday feast exhibit the typecast appearances appropriate to each school. The Stoic is grubby, with scraggly beard and unkempt hair. But the Epicurean (a man namedZenocrates [2nd-century CE]), who relies on his full beard to affect a solemn air, is ‘not neglectful of his locks. The well-coifed Epicurean stares at the harp girl with a melting, lascivious look through half-closed eyes and publicly takes her into his arms.'” (Gordon, The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus 159)

Zenocrates the Epicurean took the girl harpist in his balm, the quintessence of pleasure.’” (The Philosophy of Epicurus 247)

This is all the life there is.
It is good enough for me.
Worry won’t make another,
Or make this one last longer.
The flesh of man wastes in time.
Today there’s wine and dancing.
Today there’s flowers and women.
We might as well enjoy them.
Tomorrow — nobody knows” by Palladas of Alexandria
(Rexroth, Poems from the Greek Anthology)

Latin Amici:

It is impossible to say precisely when Epicureanism appeared at Rome. […] an obscure statement tells us, two Epicureans, Alcius and Philiscus, were expelled from Rome on the ground of immoral influence on the young. […] The earliest expositor of Epicurean in Latin was a person called Amafinius […] A host of writers sprang up in his train, and, in the words of Cicero, took possession of all Italy. But the only names recorded in literature are those of Rabirius, and Catius the Insubrian. […] There are other indications of the progress of Epicureanism at this epoch. A professor of Greek, Pompilius Andronicus, by birth a Syrian, who must have been contemporary with Lucretius, spoiled his chances as a teacher of literature by his devotion to Epicureanism. […] Amongst the circle of Cicero’sfriends there were many Epicureans — more perhaps than members of any other sect. Atticus, a wealthy, cultured, and kingly man, who steered clear of politics, stands first in the list: and with him one may join Verrius, Saufeius, PapiriusPætus, Trebatius Pansa, and Cassius, one of the assassins of Cæser. […] Phædrus, an illustrious member of the sect, contemporary with Zeno fo Sidon, its head for the time, had found his way to Rome, and about the year 90 B.C. Gave young Cicero his first philosophical lessons. […] Patro, who was now the head of the sect, wrote to Cicero […] Philodemus, another Epicurean writer of the Ciceronian epoch …” (Wallace, Epicureanism 250-255)

Amafinius was the oldest confirmed Roman Epicurean author, and Gaius Memmius was the dedicatee of the De rerum natura. Servius’s treatment of the Eclogues, and the Georgies passage, so often read as Epicurean, justifies adding Virgil to the list. Cicero’s Epicurean friends Atticus, Cassius, and Lucus Papirius Paetus are also logical choices, as is Lucius Torquatus, the Epicurean interlocutor from the De finibus.” (Palmer, Reading Lucretius in the Renaissance 151)

Appius and Lucius Saufeius were also known Epicureans who had studied in Athens under Phaedrus. The production of the works of Rabirius, Amafinius, and Catius suggests that Epicureanism was beginning to spread among non-Greek-speaking Romans.” (Montarese, Lucretius and His Sources: A Study of Lucretius, “De Rerum Natura” I 635-920 8)

In the case of Siro, Philodemus, and Amafinius the supply of biographical testimony is not generous, but it is sufficient to enable us to assign them their relative places in the context of current Epicurean activity. What is lacking, at least for Siro and Amafinius, is a record of their actual teachings. With Lucretius the situation is quite the reverse. The De rerum natura present a complete record of his philosophical output.” (Jones, Epicurean Tradition 70)

Toward the end of the century the fiery Lucilius was satirizing Titus Albucius, whom Cicero dubbed ‘a perfect Epicurean’ […] by measures taken in 92 B.C. the school of one Aurelius Opilius, freedman of a noble Epicurean, was forced to close along with the others. […] Of distinguished family also was Statilius Taurus, mentioned by Plutarch as excluded from the conspiracy against Caesar, which was headed by Cassius, both of them known to have professed the creed […] Little is known of Velleius, whom Cicero chose to be a spokesman for Epicureanism in his Book On the Nature of the Gods; he may have pursued his studies in Athens. Atticus certainly chose that city as a fit place in which to practice that Epicurean political neutrality by which he won a singular fame. Among Epicureans who pursued a similar course at home were Cicero’s friends Marius and Matius. […] Matius, a loyal Epicurean friend who defied both the assassins and their sympathizers after the tragic Ides of March” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 342-343).

Moreover, there is external evidence found mainly in the exposition of Torquatus, the Epicurean spokesman in the first and the second books of Cicero’s De finibus. Torquatus‘ account derives either from Philodemus‘ own writings or from some other source of which Philodemus would approve.” (Tsouna-McKirahan, The Ethics of Philodemus 14)

A few adherents of this philosophy were not in the party of Cæsar, and among these may be mentioned Lucius Manlius Torquatus […] Aulus Torquatus, a man of the same high character, was, we may infer, of the same sect, from the Epicurean tone of the consolation which Cicero addressed to him in exile. Saufeius, the intimate friend of Atticus, seems also to have been of good repute.” (Jerome, Aspects of the Study of Roman History 234)

On the other hand, Cicero, addressing and no doubt gently needling his friend Marcus Fabius Gallus, an Epicurean, conjures up a decidedly less heroic …” (Dynamic Reading: Studies in the Reception of Epicureanism 42)

In the late first century A.D., after the villa and library of Lucius Calpurnius Piso Caesoninus had been overwhelmed by the eruption of Vesuvius, the local aristocrat, Pollius Felix, practiced his Epicurean philosophy in his magnificent villa at Surrentum (Sorrento).” (Armstrong, Vergil, Philodemus, and the Augustans 32)

Cicero had mentioned the excellent character and record of Pansa […] As Cicero acknowledges, Pansa happened to be an Epicurean.” (Gordon, The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus 131)

Against those Epicureans who supported Caesar […] L. Piso Caesoninus and Philodemus […] C. Vibius Pansa […] and A. Hirtius, consuls in 43 BC, P. Cornelius Colabella […] the jurist C. Trebatius Testa […] P. Volumnius Eutrapelus […] and C. Matius […] must be set others who opposition to Caesar is confirmed […] L. Manlius Torquatus, consul in 65 BC, Aulus Torquatus […] L. Papirius Paetus […] M. Fadius Gallus […] Trebianus […] and Statilius […] For a good many (L. Varius Rufus, T. Pomponius Atticus, Valerius Messalla), including some who had been moderately pro-Caesar (Piso Caesoninus, Hirtius, Pansa, Trebatius Testa, Matius), declared themselves not against the liberators but against Antony and the triumvirs. Just as the tyrannicide Gaius Cassiushimself had turned Epicurean in 46 BC ‘not to enjoy the hortulus, but to reach quickly the conclusion that the tyrant had to be eliminated …” (Jones, Epicurean Tradition)

Piso’s daughter, Calpurnia Caesaris (born ca. 75), was an Epicurean, and so probably was her much younger half-brother L. Calpurnius Piso Pontifex (48 BCE—32 CE)…” (Philodemus, On Anger 7-8)

In epigram 27 Sider, Philodemus‘ patron Piso […] is asked to grace a dinner of Epicurean philosophers who rank as his [companions] on the 20th, the day of Epicurus’ birthday, and a favorite day for the school’s feasts. ( Piso’s daughter Calpurnia, Julius Caesar’s wife, had an Epicurean freedwoman Anthis who named her own son Ikadion, ‘Mr. 20th.)” (The Philosophizing Muse: The Influence of Greek Philosophy on Roman Poetry 93)

“The influence is marked by the new vogue of the word candor and the adjective candid. Horace was resorting to this new terminology when he declared that Earth had never produced ‘whiter souls’ than Virgil, Plotius, and Varius[Rufus], a trio still Epicurean […] Horace ascribed to the Epicurean Quintilius Varus, the kind but unsparing critic” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 302)

Avallone (1962, 60) writes that Maecenas was Epicurean; André (1967) believes that he was Epicurean, but not totally committed to the philosophy; Le Doze (2014) considers him to be an Epicurean, not a true Epicurean, but a Roman version of one.” (Mountford, Maecenas)

Horace’s Satires owe debts of influence to a wide range of genres and authors, including […] the moral tradition of Epicureanism.” (Yona, Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire)

In Letter 30, he [Seneca] recounts a conversation with an elderly Epicurean named Aufidius Bassus, who he says is facing the approach of death with enviable tranquility.” (Mitsis, Oxford Handbook of Epicurus and Epicureanism 501)

Along with caution and control goes the active hope of good things to come, as exemplified by the words of Cicero to the merry Epicurean Papirius Paetus: ‘You, however, as your philosophy teaches, will feel bound to hope for the best, contemplate the worst, and endure whatever shall come’” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 316).

One writer by the name of Marcus Pompilius Andronicus was more interested in his Epicurean sect than in giving special attention to matters of grammar in his writing.” (McDonald, The Biblical Canon: Its Origin, Transmission, and Authority)

In the first century of the Empire the heroism of suicide among the aristocracy in opposition to the despotism of the Caesars became associated with Stoicism, but the most dramatic of the death scenes described by Tacitus is that of the Epicurean Petronius …” (Epicurus and His Philosophy 344).

If we are to believe Cicero and Seneca, the image projected onto the Epicureans by detractors influenced the self-fashioning of later Epicureans like Apicius, Nomentanus, and Piso, who misunderstood what Epicurus meant by pleasure” (The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus 11)

Pollius Felix is an Epicurean (113), like Manlius Vopiscus of I 3 and Septimius Severus of IV 5.” Stace, P. Papinius Statius, Silvae Book II: A Commentary)

More direct evidence comes from an Epicurean character from Apamea, recorded in an inscription made by Aurelius Belius Philippus [2nd-century CE].” (King, Epicureanism and the Gospel of John: A Study of Their Compatibility 18)

Also, Alexander refused responses to anyone from Amastris in Pontus because an important citizen of that city, Lepidus, was an Epicurean with many followers.” (Gordon, Epicurus in Lycia: The Second-century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda 114)

These lines encourage Vessey […] to label Septimius Severus an Epicurean. Plausible enough.” (Birley, Septimius Severus: The African Emperor 233)

[Paul of Tarsus] was a Jew by birth, by early education an Epicurean, and by conversion a Christian” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 168)

Yet [Paul’s] youthful allegiance to the creed of Epicurus so far prevails over the convictions of his mature age that he finds it quite easy to write ‘according to nature’ and ‘contrary to nature’ and in First Corinthians 11:14 actually recognizes the principle he elsewhere repudiates: ‘Does not Nature herself teach you?’ This phraseology is foreign to the New Testament except in his Epistles. In spite of himself he shares the Epicurean slant of the public mind of the time.” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 171)

“… Paul, who in his impressionable youth had been captivated buy the siren voices of Epicurus […] When [Paul] wrote, ‘All things are lawful,’ asserting his liberty of choice, it was the ex-Epicurean who spoke.” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 176-177)

The affinity of Paul‘s teachings to those of Epicurus will become still more clear for us if we glance at the topics of fame, power, and riches, especially the last.” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 179)

The Dark Ages:

Praise be the Gods,’ exclaims the Emperor Julian, ‘for having annihilated Epicurean doctrine so completely that its books even are grown scarce.’ Naturally, in the closing struggle between paganism and Christianity, a system like Epicureanism was out of place. The only philosophy in which dying polytheism could hope to find comfort was the spiritualist doctrine of Neo-Platonism. […] From the third to the seventeenth century, Epicureanism was dormant as a system. The name, however, still survived as a stigma.” (Wallace, Epicureanism 258-260)

“… a few lines by the emperor Julian (c. 331–363), written in approximately the same period and concerning the most appropriate readings for a priest, cast a clear light on the decline that the school had already undergone at the time: Let us not admit discourses by Epicureans […] though indeed the gods have already in their wisdom destroyed their works, so that most of their books are no longer available.” (Floridi, Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission of Recovery of Pyrrhonism 13)

[B]y the middle of the fourth century [Epicureanism] would have become a virtually forgotten creed, overwhelmed, […] by the spread of Christianity, fully justifying St. Augustine’s boast that ‘its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them.’” (Jones, Epicurean Tradition 94)

In the Middle Ages […] Epicurus is represented in company with Sardanapalus, an infamous oriental voluptuary. It matter little that this charge was false.” (De Witt, St. Paul and Epicurus 22-23)

“With the rise of Christianity, Epicureanism went into decline. In the medieval period, the two primary sources of philosophical inspiration were Plato and Aristotle. The little attention that Epicurus received was usually in the service of criticizing atheistic materialism. However, Epicurean atomism was revived in the seventeenth century. […] Unsurprisingly, Christians by and large were inimical to Epicurus, and even though he was a voluminous author, few of his writing survived the Middle Ages.” (O’Keefe, Epicureanism 5-7)

Outside of strictly Christian circles the tradition of ancient philosophy shrank to a trickle but never quite perished. […] The trickle of the literary tradition was of course confined to the Byzantine region of Europe until the revival of learning int he West. On the other hand, the repudiation of Epicurus as a sensualist did not depend upon knowledge of Greek. […] In spite of Christian hostility, however, it need not be inferred that the loss of Epicurean writings was due to deliberate destruction.” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 354-355)

Medieval Amici and Vriunt:

The Emperor Frederick II (1194-1250) is in the circle of the Heretics because of the commonly held belief that he was an Epicurean.” (Alighieri, Dante’s Inferno 88)

He [Farinata degli Uberti] was of the opinion of Epicurus, that the soul dies with the body, and maintained that human happiness consisted in temporal pleasures; but he did not follow these in the way that Epicurus did, that is by making long fasts to have afterwards pleasure in eating dry bread; but was fond of good and delicate viands, and ate them without waiting to be hungry; and for this sin he is damned as a Heretic in this place.” (Boccaccio, Expositions on Dante’s Comedy)

And, again, speaking of Manfred [son of Frederick II], Villani says:—“His life was Epicurean, not believing in God or the saints, but only in corporeal delight. […] The great Epicurean of the time, in some of its good, as well as its bad senses, was the free-thinking and free-living emperor Frederick II, of whom Gregory IX wrote to the Archbishop of Canterbury, that he held it wrong for a man to believe anything which he could not prove by the force and reason of nature.” (Wallace, Epicureanism 261)

Through Manfred, the converted Epicurean, Dante may therefore highlight his polemic against those of his ‘Epicurean’ intellectual contemporaries who refused to believe in the gospel of miracles […] The Epicurean excommunicate Manfred …” (Corbett, Dante and Epicurus: A Dualistic Vision of Secular and Spiritual Fulfillment)

In line with Cicero’s treatment in De finibus, Dante elects the noble Roman Torquatus as the advocate for Epicureanism in his prose works, the Convivio and the Monarchia. Aside from the pagan Torquatus, Dante identifies four thirteenth-century magnates as ‘disciples’ of Epicurus in Inferno X: the Holy Roman Emperor Frederick II, the influential Ghibelline Cardinal Ottaviano degli Ubaldini, and the Florentine statesmen Farinata and Cavalcante dei Cavalcanti. To this list we may add Guido Cavalcanti who is indirectly associated with Epicureanism and named in the canto.” (Corbett, Dante and Epicurus: A Dualistic Vision of Secular and Spiritual Fulfillment)

Modern Friends, Amici, Amis, Vrienden, and 友達:

Three centuries later the scene has changed. Lorenzo Valla (c. 1406-1457), one of the greatest figures of the early Italian Renaissance, ventures to write a work On Pleasure in which he contrasts the Stoics with the Epicureans and declares his sympathy with the latter. That was in 1431. […] Soon after, Montaigne (1533-92) everywhere throughout his Essays, and Bruno (1548-1600) in his Degli Eroici Furori, avow themselves champions of Epicurus’s doctrine of pleasure.” (The Faith of Epicurus 149)

In one of his first writings, the De Contemptu Mundi of the 1480s, Erasmus appropriated Epicurean doctrine. He praised the Epicurean retreat from the world, politics, and marriage […] Erasmus never accepted the ascetic principle of self-denial. Instead, he openly praised the Epicurean stress on modest pleasures, telling the dedicatee that ‘indeed, the whole rationale (ratioI) of our life is Epicurean!’” (Monfasani, Renaissance Humanist, from the Middle Ages to Modern Times)

“… the first two great Epicureans of the Renaissance were Michel de Montaigne (1533-92) in France and Francesco Guicciardini (1483-1540) in Italy. Epicurean in everything, as man and as poet, was the early classicist Ludovico Ariosto (1474-1533). But not until the French abbot Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655) was the system of Epicurus to rise again in its entirety—this time, however, by approaching truth through faith.” (Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 31)

The glory of the Holy See under the highly educated humanist and Epicurean Leo X knew few limits.” (Hagan, What Great Paintings Say 118)

The Epicurean critique of religion, combined with the Epicurean accounts of the self-formation of the cosmos and the spontaneous emergence of living forms on earth, had a significant impact on European philosophy of the 17th and 18th centuries. […] there was a decided attempt at this time to articulate the notion of a creator God of infinite power whose responsibility for the world is exhausted in the initial instantaneous act of creation […] a challenging task set for philosophers by a Pope with definite Epicurean leanings, Leo X.” (Wilson, Epicureanism: A Very Short Introduction)

Desbarreaux, La Fare, Chaulieu, Chapelle, Dehenault, and Mme Deshoulières […] La Fontaine […] It is justifiable to refer to them as a school of Epicurean poets; a network of correspondaence in prose and verse links them together.” (Spink, French Free-Thought from Gassendi to Voltaire 152)

Pascal condemns Des Barreaux’s Epicurean thought and audacious behavior. The libertine Des Barreaux, like Théophile de Viau before him […] Epicurean libertines, like Des Barreaux …” (Boitano, The Polemics of Libertine Conversion in Pascal’s Pensées 119)

The work was preceded by a prefatory letter to François Luillier (c. 1600—51) who was something of a Maecenas and had the reputation of being a practicing Epicurean in ordinary life.” (Spink, French Free-Thought from Gassendi to Voltaire 138)

Parisian Epicureans of the early seventeenth century included Gabriel Naudé, Elio Diodatai and François de la Mothe le Vayer, and, on the periphery, the storywriter Cyrano de Bergerac, and the playwright Moliére.” (The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism 268)

The general view of Cyrano [de Bergerac] that he was a disciple of Gassendi, may require no correction, but he went far beyond Gassendi in the daring of his Epicurean naturalism.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-172973)

Gilles de Launay, a professor of philosophy and historiographe du roi, began his Introduction a la philosophie, […] by invoking Epicurus as the ideal model of the natural philosopher. […] He was what all philosophers should aspire to be: He had ‘withdrawn from commerce with the world,’ seeking a happiness of the mind that was ‘very pure and very innocent.’ He was ‘this great genius of Greece . . . [and] the great master of ethics.’” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 59)

“Epicureanism resurged at different times, though usually with regard to this or that particular aspect of its doctrines. A fuller resurgence, which some have called neo-Epicureanism, took place in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Its most notable representatives were the French philosophers Claude Gillermet de Bérigard (CE 1578–1663), Emmanual Maignan (CE 1601–76), and Pierre Gassendi (CE 1592–1655), who advocated a fuller version of Epicureanism than the others.” (Iannone, Dictionary of World Philosophy 175)

“In this, [Gassendi] was followed by Saint-Evremond, by Sarasin, and by a whole long line of epicurean poets—Dehénault, Mme Deshoulières, La Fare, and Chaulier—which in fact extended from Théophile de Viau to Chaulieu and thence to Voltaire.” (Wade, Intellectual Origins of the French Enlightenment 229)

The Epicureanism of the likes of Ninon de Lenclos, Marion de Lorme, the Marquis de Sévigné and the La Fares, the Chaulieus, the Saint-Evremonds, in short, of the whole of that delightful company of souls […] their Epicureanism, I say, somewhat altered the tone of fiction.” (de Sade, The Crimes of Love: Heroic and Tragic Tales, Preceded by an Essay on Novels 305)

Théophile is thus a perfect Epicurean by birth and by principle, an Epicurean in the diversity and the brevity of his enjoyments, an Epicurean in the prudent and wise administration of his pleasures.” (Hallays, The Spell of the Heart of France 165)

Thus, if our melancholy Epicurean [Jean Dehénault] has left few traces of his literary talents, he has at least the somewhat remarkable distinction of having written a piece of prose which passed as the word of Saint-Évremond, and perhaps a play which men of taste have thought was Molière’s.” (Aldington, Literary Studies and Reviews 97)

The poet Jean-François Sarasin, in a ‘Discours de morale’ devoted to Epicurus […] attributed the fact that ‘Epicurus fell into public hatred’ to the ignorance, prejudice, and hasty verdict of his judges (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 10)

Montaigne writes with the mellowed and kindly cynicism of an Epicurean sage. […] The most conspicuous of these efforts [to rehabilitate Epicureanism] was the exposition and adaptation of the Epicurean system by Pierre Gassendi(1592-1655). […] The lighter graces and easy-going morality of Epicureanism found a skillful advocate in St. Evremond, whose letters to the modern Leontion, as he calls Ninon de l’Enclose, give what we may style the French-novel version of the liaison between Epicurus and his lady disciple.” (Wallace, Epicureanism 263-264)

Similarly, the ostensibly fideistic Antoine Menjot, in his Opusculus post humes (1697), urged his readers to see Epicurus and Gassendi as in many ways the most pious of the ancient and modern philosophers, respectively.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 60)

“ … an erudite and closely argued case for seeing La Rochefoucauld as an Epicurean, continuing the antistoical Pyrrhonism of the later Montaigne.” (Barish, The Antitheatrical Prejudice 211)

The ‘baptism’ of Epicurus was the achievement of the French philosopher Pierre Gassendi […] Walter Charleton was the most significant disseminator of Epicureanism in England, drawing on him in both his moral and natural philosophy […] A translation of Antoine Le Grand’s early work on Epicurean philosophy was published in 1676 as Divine Epicurus, or, The Empire of Pleasure over the Virtues.” (Hutton, British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century61)

Cavendish‘s friend, Walter Charleton, the main vector for Epicurean philosophy in England, edited and published J.B. van Helmont’s A Ternary of Paradoxes, which discussed corpuscular effluvia, in 1650.” (The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism, 268)

The Cartesian Antoine Le Grand, along with Walter Charleton, and later Charles de Marguetel de Saint Denis, sieur de Saint-Évremond, promoted openly Epicurean systems of morals. They insisted that Epicurus had been unjustly maligned by his enemies, and the earlier image of the Epicurean pig swilling in a filthy trough was replaced by a new image of the Epicurean as a man of taste, refinement and delicate feeling” (The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism, 278)

As Catherine Wilson in her study of Epicurean reception laconically remarks, while intellectual historians have been unable to gauge the exact sources of Locke’s epistemology, he ‘owned two copies of Diogenes Lartius’ Lives, three copies of On the Nature of Things‘ and ‘was associated with well-known Gassendists François Bernier and Gilles de Launay.’” (Dynamic Reading: Studies in the Reception of Epicureanism 175)

“ … many readers, even if they did not read Gassendi directly, indeed were deeply familiar with François Bernier’sAbrege […] was one of the learned world’s most significant Epicurean voices.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 59)

The word ‘pleasure’ recalls to mind the name of Epicurus, and I confess, that of all the opinions of the philosophers concerning the supreme good, there are none which appear to me to be so reasonable as his.” (L’enclos, Life, Letters and Epicurean Philosophy of Ninon de L’Enclos)

La Fontaine shared the Epicurean view that the happy man is one who lives a simple, trouble-free life, retired from the world, where, like the brute beasts who are cared for by nature, he has just what he needs and no more.” (Calder, The Fables of La Fontaine: Wisdom Brought Down to Earth 150)

All the Fables are steeped in La Fontaine’s Epicurean humanism, his passion for liberty, for friendship …” (Blackham, The Fable as Literature 123)

Cavendish ‘expounded an Epicurean atomism at once so extreme and fanciful that she shocked the enemies of atomism, and embarrassed its friends.’ […] But Cavendish was not a classic Epicurean.” (Sarasohn, The Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish 35)

The epicurean poet, Antoinette Deshoulières (1634–1694), a disciple of the atomist natural philosopher Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) could also be considered a libertine.” (Stanton, The Dynamics of Gender in Early Modern France 33)

By far the most outstanding of the Epicurean poets in Chaulieu, the man whom Voltaire called his master. He was the acknowledged leader of the Epicureans of the Temple. […] His thought was more truly Epicurean in the strictly philosophical sense of the word than one would have expected in a light poet.” (Rozenblum, A Seventeenth-century Epicurean Poet: Guillaume Amfrye de Chaulieu 3)

Wilson also mentions the attraction of seventeenth-century women intellectuals (including Margaret Cavendish,Lucy Hutchinson [a devoted Puritan and Calvinist], and Aphra Behn) to Epicureanism.” (Dynamic Reading: Studies in the Reception of Epicureanism 137)

Guillaume Lamy (1644 – 1683) was a self-proclaimed Epicurean, a philosopher and physician based in Paris, who published his major works between the late 1660s and the late 1670s.” (Early Modern Medicine and Natural Philosophy 355)

The most prominent heterodox neo-Epicurean was Guillaume Lamy, doctor-regent of the Faculty of Medicine of the University of Paris.” (Kors, Epicurean and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 49)

Toward the end of the grand siècle La Fare, the Epicurean and inseparable friend of the Abbé de Chaulieu, translated the famous second ode.” (Robinson, Sappho and Her Influence: Volume 2 168)

The yet more successful translation of Lucretius’s poem into French was by the baron Jacques Parrain Des Coutures […] While noting that the Christian obviously would reject the Epicurean denial of an afterlife as manifestly false, it urged readers to recognize the value of the Epicurean views of ethics and the force of the Epicurean assault against superstition and polytheism.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 34)

In 1678 he discussed his political theory of religious revolutions with the Epicurean libertine, court poet and dramatist John Wilmot, the Earl of Rochester, who rejected immortality and providence.” (Hudson, The English Deists: Studies in Early Enlightenment 68)

The controversial Epicurean moralist, Bernard Mandeville, makes a distinction between Christian Epicureans like Erasmus, Gassendi and Temple, who claim that piety and virtue are the only true sources of voluptas, and libertines such as Hobbes’s follower Charles de Saint-Évremond, who associate it with more straightforwardly sensual pleasure.” (Bullard, Edmund Burke and the Art of Rhetoric 91)

In 1685 the English Epicurean Sir William Temple signaled a very different attitude by abandoning a promising early diplomatic career and retiring to his garden at Moor Park in Surrey, there to devote himself to writing moral essays (including Upon the Garden of Epicurus) and raising apricots.” (Most, The Classical Tradition 323)

François Courtin, who was given the abbey of Mont-Saint-Quentin at the age of nineteen, was a poet and Epicurean described by Voltaire as ‘big, fat, round, short, and lazy.’” (Buchan, John Law: A Scottish Adventurer of the Eighteenth Century 1753)

Congreve wrote all of his plays during the 1690s, when he was in his twenties, and under the influence of his Epicurean philosophy of self-restrained morality.” (Trumbach, Sex and the Gender Revolution, Volume 1: Heterosexuality and the Third Gender in Enlightenment London 77)

He [Rousseau] belonged to a school which is traceable to Chapelle, the father of French epicurean poetry.” (Hutson, A History of French Literature 146)

As evidenced by the use of Guillaume Lamy by Julien Offray de La Mettrie, this neo-Epicurean influence played a significant role in the development of a later Enlightenment materialism.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650-1729 49)

There is more than enough to suggest that its author [Celestino Galiani] was committed to a moderate, Christian Epicureanism, in which morality and natural law were in accordance with men’s natural desire for the pleasures …” (Robertson, The Case for the Enlightenment 206)

Frederick [the Great] replies to Sweerts that he is only too happy to obey, for he loves all the pleasures condemned by “un faux mystique” (Christianity) and would always follow the Epicurean gospel.” (Blanning, Frederick the Great: King of Prussia 156-157)

Diderot denounces the way this philosophical perspective had been vilified and misrepresented as vulgar hedonism […] Diderot, a partisan of the Epicurean rather than the Cartesian understanding of matter, challenged Descartes’ plenum of vortices and whirlpools …” (Kavanagh, Enlightened Pleasures: Eighteenth-Century France and the New Epicureanism 4-5)

Epicurean theory […] was used to state perhaps the central naturalistic doctrine of Holbach’s text: ‘The indestructible elements, the atoms of Epicurus, whose movement, concourse, and combinations have produced all beings, are, without doubt, more real causes than the God of theology” […] Holbach, by intellectual spirit, deep philosophical family resemblance, and reflective temperament, was indeed an Epicurean disciple.” (Kors, Epicureans and Atheists in France 1650-1729 201)

“ … As you say of yourself, I too am an Epicurean. I consider the genuine (not the imputed) doctrines of Epicurus as containing every thing rational in moral philosophy which Greece and Rome have left us.” (Thomas Jefferson, Letter To William Short, October 31st, 1819)

The fundamental starting point of Bentham’s theory was thus the observation […] that ‘nature has placed man under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure’. Associating pleasure with happiness and pain with unhappiness then, Bentham maintained that ‘[p]leasure … and the avoidance of pains, are the ends which the legislator has in view’. For him, questions of ethical conduct, or indeed just legislation, lay in measuring happiness, and for this reason, he is right labelled an Epicurean.” (Jeffery, Reason and Emotion in International Ethics 105)

June 26th, Delbury.—I rode to Downton Castle on Monday, a gimcrack castle and bad bouse built by Payne Knight, an epicurean philosopher, who after building the cast went and lived in a lodge of cottage in the park: there he died, not without suspicion of having put an end to himself, which would have been fully conformable to his notions.” (Greville, The Greville Memoirs 190)

Given what Bentham says later about his formative influences, one of these Epicurean writers, and perhaps the most important, was the French materialist philosopher Claude Adrien Helvétius.” (Bentham and the Arts 24)

A typical more modern Epicurean, in theory if not in practice, is Walter Savage Landor. He is typical at any rate in his enthusiasm for the atomic philosophy and the personality of Epicurus, and his hostility to Plato.” (Shorey, Platonism, Ancient and Modern 18)

Then there was Charles Greville […] a friend when friendship was most wanted; high born, high bred, avowedly Epicurean …” (Taylor, Autobiography of Henry Taylor. 1800-1875: Volume 1 315)

Wright’s novel, in which she implicitly advanced her own arguments against organized religion and for women’s equality, had offered a favorable account of the unfairly maligned Epicurus and his Garden […] Wright’s epicurean critique of religion …” (Hull, Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers 472)

But in its frank acceptance of the realities of our human life, and of the laws of universal nature—in its emphasis on friendly love as the great help in moral progress—and in its rejection of the asceticism which mistakes penance for discipline, Epicureanism proclaimed elements of truth which the world cannot afford to lose.” (Wallace, Epicureanism270)

Heavily influenced by the Epicurean hedonism, Guyau emphasized the principle and power of life that naturally lead the human beings to moral decisions.” (Lee, Ham Sok Hon’s Ssial Cosmopolitan Vision 17)

M. Guyau treats Epicureanism mainly as the ancient forerunner of utilitarian and hedonistic theories. Signor Trezza gives a somewhat idealized picture of it, as the ancient gospel of a full and free humanity, living in the perception of the great law of nature and of love, and anticipating by two thousand years the advent of true philosophy.” (Wallace,Epicureanism 266)

As to the word spiritual, I frankly don’t know what it means. The dictionary tells me that spirit ‘is the intelligent or immaterial part of man, soul.’ I look up soul and learn that it is ‘the immaterial part of man.’ And that spiritual means “of spirit, as opposed to matter, I am on the side of the materialists.” (Sedgwick, Memoirs of an Epicurean 156)

‘[L]ife is linked with sensation and cannot be understood except through sensation […] in human affairs, Epicureanism is the only natural ethics which does not demand profound or subtle reasoning.’” (Holmes, “Reviewed Work: Sensation: The Origin of Life by Charles Leopold Mayer” 118-119)

Tsuji was not devoted to massively propagating ideas of class war […] Tsuji was instead an Epicurean, seeking a simple lifestyle and reveling in a peaceful enjoyment of modest pleasures, both physical, social, and intellectual. […] Tsuji was not interested in striving for monetary wealth and fame as the foundations for his happiness. Rather, the ability to live freely, play his flute, and socialize were his espoused means to wellbeing and he did not feel bound by some sort of civic duty.” (Erana Jae Taylor, Tsuji Jun: Japanese Dadaist, Anarchist, Philosopher, Monk 2)

“…it is plain that [humanity’s] only logical goal […] is simply the achievement of a reasonable equilibrium which shall enhance his likelihood of experiencing the sort of reactions he wishes, and which shall help along his natural impulse […] Here, then, is a practical and imperative system of ethics, resting on the firmest possible foundation and being essentially that taught by Epicurus and Lucretius.” (H. P. Lovecraft, Selected Letters, Volume 5, 241)

Christopher Hitchens also declared himself an Epicurean …” (Evans, Philosophy for Life and Other Dangerous Situations: Ancient Philosophy for Modern Problems 91)

Onfray is anarchistic in proclivity, yet above all, and concomitantly, he is a hedonistic Epicurean.” (Quadrio, New Atheism: Critical Perspectives and Contemporary Debates 151)

Fragmentary Attestations:

ANTIGENES (first century BC)
Antigenes was a friend of Philodemus of Gadara and probably also an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 27)

ANTIPATER (first century AD?)
Antipater was an Epicurean and a friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 27)

ANTIPHANES (third/second century BC)
Antiphanes was an Epicurean who for unknown reasons fell out with the school.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 28)

ANTONIUS (second century BC)
Antonius was an Epicurean who exchanged views with Galen on medical matters.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 30)

APOLLODORUS [of Lampsacus] [1] (fourth century BC)
Apollodorus was an Epicurean and a brother of Leontius of Lampsacus.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 31)

APOLLODORUS [the Epicurean] [2] (third century BC)
Apollodorus was an Epicurean, perhaps a pupil of Polystratus.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 31)

APOLLODORUS [of Athens] [4] (second century BC)
Apollodorus was an Epicurean, heading the school for most of the second half of the second century BC. His long tenure earned him the nickname of ‘Tyrant of the Garden’. He wrote many books, including a life of Epicurus, and was the teacher of Zeno of Sidon.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 31)

APOLLONIDES [2] (third century BC)
Apollonides was an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 32)

APOLLOPHANES OF PERGAMUM (first century BC)
Apollophanes was an Epicurean and a leading citizen of Pergamum, sent on a mission to Rome on his city’s behalf.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 35)

AMYNIAS OF SAMOS (first century BC/first century AD)
Amynias was an Epicurean and priest at the temple of Hera on Samos.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 21)

ANAXARCHUS (fourth/third century BC)
According to Plutarch of Chaeronea, Anaxarchus was the recipient of a letter from Epicurus. He is assumed to have been an Epicurean himself.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 22)

ARCEPHON [1] (fourth/third century BC)
Arcephon was an Epicurean and the recipient of a letter from Epicurus himself.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 36)

ARISTONYMUS [2] (third/second century BC)
Aristonymus was an Epicurean and a friend of Dionysius [3].”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 36)

ARTEMON [1] (third/second century BC)
Artemon was an Epicurean and the teacher of Philonides of Laodicea.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 51)

ATHENAEUS [1] (second/first century BC)
Athenaeus was an Epicurean, a pupil of Polyaenus of Lampsacus.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 54)

ATHENOGORUS [1] (second/first century BC)
Athenogorus was an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 55)

ATHENODORUS OF ATHENS (first century AD)
Athenodorus was an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 56)

ARTEMIDORUS OF PARIUM (first century BC/first century AD)
Artemidorus wrote a book on celestial phenomena with which Seneca entirely disagreed. He may have been an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 50)

BACCHUS (first century BC)
Bacchius was a friend of Philodemus of Gadara and probably also an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 59)

BALBUS, LUCIUS CORNELIUS (first century BC)
Balbus came from Gades (Cadiz) in Spain and went on to become the first foreign-born consul of Rome in 40 BC. He became a friend of Cicero, who successfully defended him in a legal action. Comments made by Cicero suggest he was an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 59)

BASSUS, LUCIUS AUFIDIUS (first century BC)
According to Seneca, Bassus was an Epicurean who bore witness to his school’s teaching in a way he coped with prolonged ill health. He was an historian but none of his writings have survived.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 59)

CALLISTRATUS (third century BC?)
Callistratus was an Epicurus.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 69)

CELER, CAIUS ARTORIUS (first or second century AD)
Celer was an Epicurean philosopher from North Africa.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 72)

CELSUS [1] (first century AD)
Celer was an Epicurean who lived during the time of Nero.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 73)

CELSUS [2] (second century AD)
Celsus was an Epicurean and friend of Lucian of Samosata.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 73)

CEPHISOPHON (second century BC?)
Cephisophon was an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 74)

CHARMIDES [2] (fourth/third century BC)
Charmides was an Epicurean and a friend of Arcesilaus of Pitane.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 74)

CINEAS (third century BC)
Cineas was an advisor to Pyrrhus, the king of Epirus. He was clearly well-versed in philosophy and may have been an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 79)

CRONIUS OF LAMPSACUS (fourth/third century BC)
Cronius studied under Eudoxus of Cnidus before becoming an Epicurean and correspondent of Epicurus.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 88)

DAMIS [2] (second century AD)
Damis is an Epicurean mentioned by Lucian of Samosata. Opinions are divides as to whether he is to be regarded as an historical figure or not.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 100)

DAMOPHANES (second century BC?)
Damophanes was probably an Epicurean. His name appears in fragments of a text in which an Epicurean position on religion is articulated.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 91)

DEMETRIA (fourth/third century BC)
Demetria was a member of the community of Epicurus and the female companion to Hermarchus of Mitylene.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 93)

DIODORUS [3] (third century BC)
Diodorus was an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 100)

DIODORUS [5] (first century AD)
Diodorus was an Epicurean who committed suicide in a state of contentment and with a clear conscience, according to Seneca.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 100)

DION [2] (first century BCE)
Dion appears to have been an Epicurean with whom Cicero was acquainted but for whom he had little time or respect.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 105)

DIONYSIUS OF RHODES (first century AD?)
Dionysius was an Epicurean and a friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 107)

DIOTIMUS OF SEMACHIDES (third century BC)
Diotimus was an Epicurean in Athens and perhaps the pupil of Polystratus.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 109)

DOLABELLA, PUBLIUS CORNELIUS (first century BC)
Dolabella was an Epicurean and for a time the son-in-law of Cicero. Politically active, he achieved the dubious distiction of being pronounced a public enemy b y the Roman Senate. In 43 BC, utterly defeated, he ordered one of his soldiers to kill him.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 109)

DOSITHEUS (fourth/third century BC)
Dositheus was probably an Epicurean. A letter written to him by Epicurus on the death of his son Hegesianax [2] was copied by Diogenes of Oenoanda. His name sometimes appears as Sositheus.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 111)

DOSSENNUS
Dossennus appears to have been a philosopher, perhaps an Epicurean. Seneca mentions a monument to him with an inscription testifying to his wisdom.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 111)

EGNATIUS (first century BC)
Egnatius was an Epicurean who wrote a poem On the Nature of Things. It bears some resemblances to the work of the same name by Lucretius and is generally thought to have been written after it.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 113)

EPICURIUS (first/second century AD)
Epicurius was an Epicurean who appears in a work by Plutarch of Chaeronea.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 116)

EUDEMUS (fourth century BC)
Eudemus was an Epicurean mentioned in a letter by Epicurus.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 121)

EUGATHES (third century BC?)
Eugathes was a barber from Thessaly who abandoned cutting hair in order to become an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 123)

EXUPERANTIA (third/fourth century AD)
Exuperantia was a philosopher in Hadrumetum. Like her husband, Heraclamon Leonides, she was probably an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 131)

HAURANUS, CAIUS STALLIUS (first century BC/first century AD?)
Hauranus was a member of the Epicurean community of Neapolis (Naples).
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 138)

HEGESIANAX [2] (third century BC)
Hegesianax was probably an Epicurean. The son of Dositheus and brother of Pyrson, he died young and Epicurus sent a letter of consolation to his family.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 139)

HERACLAMON LEONIDES (third/fourth century AD)
Heraclamon was an Epicurean from Hadrumetum. His wife was Exuperantia.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 139)

HELIODORUS [2] (first/second century AD)
Heliodorus was an Epicurean and close friend of the emperor Hadrian. He succeeded Popillius Theotimus as head of the school in Athens.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 139)

HELIODORUS OF ANTIOCH (third/second century BC)
Heliodorus was an Epicurean who held a senior position at the court of Seleucus IV. He fell out with the king over a political matter and assassinated him.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 139)

HERACLITUS OF RHODIAPOLIS (first century AD)
Heraclitus was a physician, poet and Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 144)

HIPPOCLIDES (fourth/third century BC)
Hippoclides was an Epicurean. According to Valerius Maximus, he was born on the same day as Polystratus, was close to him all his life, and died on the same day as he did.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 152)

HIRTIUS, AULUS (first century BC)
Hirtius was an Epicurean and a correspondent of Cicero, although none of their letters survive.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 154)

IOLAUS OF BITHYNIA (second century BC)
Iolaus was a physician and perhaps an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 158)

IRENAEUS OF MILETUS (second/first century BC)
Irenaeus was an Epicurean and a pupil of Demetrius Lacon.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 158)

LUCCESIUS, LUCIUS (first century BC)
Lucceius was an historian and a friend of Cicero. Some of Cicero’s letters to Lucceius suggest that he may have been an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 170)

LYCOPHRON [2] (fourth/third century BC)
According to Plutarch of Chaeronea, Lycophron was an Epicurean. Leontius of Lampsacus corresponded with him.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 172)

MAXIMUS [1] (first/second century AD)
Maximus was an Epicurean and a friend of Pliny the Younger. He was sent to Rome to reform the constitutions of Greek cities. He was an acquaintance of Epictetus and a supposed discussion between them is preserved in Discourses III.7.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 178)

MENESTRATUS (fourth/third century BC)
Menestratus was an Epicurean, a pupil of Metrodorus of Lampsacus.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 185)

MENNEAS (first century AD?)
Menneas was an Epicurean and a friend of Diogenes of Oenoanda.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 185)

MESSALLA CORVINUS, MARCUS VALERIUS (first century BC)
Messalla was an Epicurean and a friend of Horace. As young men, they studied together in Athens. He opposed Julius Caesar but eventually made his peace with Augustus. As an author he wrote a number of works, including philosophical treatises, but none survive.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 185)

NERO (second/first century BC)
Demetrius Lacon dedicated a book to Nero, making it likely he was an Epicurean himself.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 194

OPILLUS, AURELIUS (second century BC)
Opillus was originally the slave of an Epicurean and may have been one himself. In any event, when he was freed he became a teacher of philosophy, although he later switched to rhetoric and grammar. When Publius Rutilius Rufus was sent into exile, Opillus went with him.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 201)

PLATO OF SARDIS (first century BC)
Plato was an Epicurean who taught in Athens.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 223)

POLLIUS FELIX (first century AD)
Pollius was an Epicurean and a patron of the poet Statius.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 223)

PUDENTIANUS (second century AD?)
Pudentianus was an Epicurean. Galen wrote a lost work about him.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 236)

PYRSON (third century BC)
Pyrson was the son of Dositheus and brother of Hegesianax [2]. He was probably an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 238)

VOLUMNIUS EUTRAPELUS, PUBLIUS (first century BC)
Volumnius was a friend of Cicero and Marcus Brutus. According to Plutarch of Chaeronea he was also a philosopher, and it seems most likely that he was an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 238)

SISENNA, LUCUIUS CORNELIUS (second/first century BC)
Sisenna achieved acclaim as an historian. Cicero suggests he was an Epicurean, but not a very consistent one.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 249)

THEODORIDAS OF LINDUS (first century AD?)
Theodoridas was a philosophical acquaintance of Diogenes of Oenoanda. He was probably an Epicurean.”
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 263)

THEOPHEIDES (third century BC)
Theopheides was a friend of Hermarchus of Mitylene. Hermarchus wrote him a letter in which he attacked Alexinus of Elis. It seems likely Theopheides was an Epicurean
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 266)

TIMAGORAS (first century BC)
Timagoras was an Epicurean mentioned by Cicero.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 266)

TREBIANUS (first century BC)
Trebianus was a friend of Cicero who took an interest in philosophy and may have been an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 274)

TUCCA, PLAUTIUS (first century BC)
Tucca was an Epicurean, a pupil of both Philodemus of Gadara and Siro. Virgil and Horace were amongst his friends and he edited the manuscript of Virgil’s Aeneid when the poet died.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 247)

ZENOBIUS (second/third century AD)
Zenobius was an Epicurean, the target of a lost book by Alexander of Aphrodisias.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 285)

ZOPYRUS (fourth/third century BC)
Carneiscus dedicated a book about friendship to Zopyrus, suggesting he was probably an Epicurean.
(Curnow, The Philosophers of the Ancient Worlds: An A-Z Guide 285)

Thanks to my Epicurean friends.

– Nate

Works Cited

Ahlholm, Tuuli. Philosophers in Stone: Philosophy and Self-Representation in Epigraphy of the Roman Empire. 2017. University of Oxford.

Aldington, Richard. Literary Studies and Reviews. United Kingdom, Allen & Unwin, 1924.

Allen, Prudence. The Concept of Woman: The Aristotelian Revolution, 750 B.C. – A. D. 1250. United Kingdom, Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1997.

Alighieri, Dante. Dante’s Inferno. Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1995.

Armstrong, David, and Mcosker, Michael. Philodemus, On Anger. United States, SBL Press, 2020.

Armstrong, David. Vergil, Philodemus, and the Augustans. N.p., University of Texas Press, 2010.

Athénée. Athenaeus. The Deipnosophists: Book III (Continued), IV, V. United Kingdom, Heinemann, 1928.

Barish, Jonas A.. The Antitheatrical Prejudice. United Kingdom, University of California Press, 1985.

Barnes, Jonathan, et al. The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Bentham and the Arts. United Kingdom, UCL Press, 2020.

Birley, Anthony R.. Hadrian: The Restless Emperor. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2013.

Birley, Anthony R. Septimius Severus: The African Emperor. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2002.

Blackham, Harold John. The Fable as Literature. United Kingdom, Bloomsbury Publishing, 2014.

Blanning, T. C. W.. Frederick the Great: King of Prussia. United Kingdom, Random House, 2016.

Boccaccio, Giovanni. Expositions on Dante’s Comedy. United States, University of Toronto Press, 2009.

Boitano, John F.. The Polemics of Libertine Conversion in Pascal’s Pensées: A Dialectics of Rational and Occult Libertine Beliefs. Germany, Gunter Narr Verlag, 2002.

Buchan, James. John Law: A Scottish Adventurer of the Eighteenth Century. United Kingdom, Quercus, 2018.

Bullard, Paddy. Edmund Burke and the Art of Rhetoric. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2011.

Calder, Andrew. The Fables of La Fontaine: Wisdom Brought Down to Earth. Switzerland, Droz, 2001.

Castner, Catherine J.. Prosopography of Roman Epicureans from the Second Century B.C. to the Second Century A.D.. Germany, P. Lang, 1988.

Cicero, Marcus Tullius. Cicero: On Moral Ends. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2001.

Clay, Diskin. Paradosis and survival: three chapters in the history of Epicurean philosophy. Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 1998.

Corbett, George. Dante and Epicurus: A Dualistic Vision of Secular and Spiritual Fulfillment. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2017.

Courtney, William Leonard. Studies in Philosophy: Ancient and Modern. United Kingdom, Rivingtons, 1882.

Crespo, Hiram. Tending the Epicurean Garden. United States, American Humanist Association, 2014.

Curnow, Trevor. The philosophers of the ancient world: an A to Z guide. London, Bloomsbury Academic, 2006.

de Sade, Marquis. The Crimes of Love: Heroic and Tragic Tales, Preceded by an Essay on Novels. United Kingdom, Oxford University Press, UK, 2005.

De Witt, Norman Wentworth. Epicurus and His Philosophy. United Kingdom, University of Minnesota Press, 1964.

De Witt, Norman Wentworth. St. Paul and Epicurus. United Kingdom, U.M.I. Books on Demand, 1993.

Dynamic Reading: Studies in the Reception of Epicureanism. United Kingdom, Oxford University Press, 2012.

Early Modern Medicine and Natural Philosophy. Germany, Springer Netherlands, 2015.

Epicurus. The Philosophy of Epicurus, edited by Strodach, George K. United States, Dover Publications, 2019.

Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2011.

Evans, Jules. Philosophy for Life and Other Dangerous Situations: Ancient Philosophy for Modern Problems. United States, New World Library, 2013.

Farrington, Benjamin. The Faith of Epicurus. United Kingdom, Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1967.

Floridi, Luciano. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. United States, An American Philological Association Book, 2002.

Frischer, Bernard. The sculpted word : Epicureanism and philosophical recruitment in Ancient Greece. Berkeley, University of California Press, 1982.

Gordon, Pamela. Epicurus in Lycia: the second-century world of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 1996.

Gordon, Pamela. The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus. United States, University of Michigan Press, 2012.

Gruen, Erich S.. Studies in Greek culture and Roman policy. United Kingdom, University of California Press, 1996.

Hagen, Rainer, and Hagen, Rose-Marie. What Great Paintings Say. Germany, Taschen, 2003.

Hallays, André. The Spell of the Heart of France. Outlook Verlag, 2020.

Harland, Philip A.. North Coast of the Black Sea, Asia Minor. Germany, De Gruyter, 2014.

Holmes, Eugene C. “Reviewed Work: Sensation: The Origin of Life by Charles Leopold Mayer.”Science & Society 27, 1, 1963, 118-119.

Hudson, Wayne. The English Deists: Studies in Early Enlightenment. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2015.

Hutson, Charles Woodward. A History of French Literature. United States, John B. Alden, 1889.

Hutton, Sarah. British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century. United Kingdom, OUP Oxford, 2015.

Hull, Richard T.. Dictionary Of Modern American Philosophers. United Kingdom, Bloomsbury Academic, 2005.

Iannone, A. Pablo. Dictionary of World Philosophy. Taylor & Francis, 2013.

Jefferson, Thomas. Letter, 1819 October 31, Monticello, [Albemarle County, Virginia] to [William Short]. United States, 1819.

Jeffery, Renée. Reason and Emotion in International Ethics. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2014.

Jerome, Thomas Spencer. Aspects of the Study of Roman History. United Kingdom, G. P. Putnam’s sons, 1923.

Jones, Howard. The Epicurean Tradition. United Kingdom, Routledge, 1989.

Kavanagh, Thomas M.. Enlightened Pleasures: Eighteenth-Century France and the New Epicureanism. United States, Yale University Press, 2010.

King, Fergus J.. Epicureanism and the Gospel of John: A Study of Their Compatibility. Germany, Mohr Siebeck, 2020.

Konstan, Professor David, and Konstan, David. Friendship in the Classical World. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 1997.

Kors, Alan Charles. Epicureans and Atheists in France, 1650–1729. United States, Cambridge University Press, 2016.

Lovecraft, Howard Phillips, and Turner, James. Selected Letters. United States, Arkham House, 1971.

Mayo, Thomas Franklin. Epicurus in England (1650-1725). United States, Columbia University, 1934.

McDonald, Lee Martin. The Biblical Canon: Its Origin, Transmission, and Authority. United States, Baker Publishing Group, 2006.

Ménage, Gilles, and Zedler, Beatrice Hope. The history of women philosophers. United Kingdom, University Press of America, 1984.

Mitsis, Phillip. Oxford Handbook of Epicurus and Epicureanism. United Kingdom, Oxford University Press, 2020.

Monfasani, John. Renaissance Humanism, from the Middle Ages to Modern Times. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2016.

Montarese, Francesco. Lucretius and His Sources: A Study of Lucretius, “De Rerum Natura” I 635-920. Germany, De Gruyter, 2012.

Most, Glenn W, et al. The Classical Tradition. Norway, Harvard University Press, 2010

Mountford, Peter. Maecenas. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2019.

O’Keefe, Tim. Epicureanism. United Kingdom, University of California Press, 2010.

Palmer, Ada. Reading Lucretius in the Renaissance. United Kingdom, Harvard University Press, 2014.

Poems from the Greek Anthology. United States, University of Michigan Press, 1962.

Laertius, Diogenes. Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. United Kingdom, Oxford University Press, 2018.

Lee, Song-Chong. Ham Sok Hon’s Ssial Cosmopolitan Vision. United States, Lexington Books, 2020.

Quadrio, Philip A., and Tuckett, Jonathan. New Atheism: Critical Perspectives and Contemporary Debates. Germany, Springer International Publishing, 2017.

Reid, James Smith, and Cicero, Marcus Tullius. M. Tulli Ciceronis Academica. United Kingdom, Macmillan, 1885.

Robertson, John. The Case for The Enlightenment: Scotland and Naples 1680–1760. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Robinson, David Moore. Sappho and Her Influence: Volume 2. India, Marshall Jones Company, 1924.

Roller, Duane W., and Strabo. The Geography of Strabo: An English Translation, with Introduction and Notes. United Kingdom, Cambridge University Press, 2014.

Rozenblum, E.. A Seventeenth-century Epicurean Poet: Guillaume Amfrye de Chaulieu. United Kingdom, University of London (Bedford College), 1956.

Sanders, Kirk R. “On a Causal Notion in Philodemus’ On Anger. Classical Quarterly 59, no. 2 (2009): 642-47.

Sarasohn, Lisa T.. The Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish: Reason and Fancy During the Scientific Revolution. United States, Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010.

Sedgwick, Henry Dwight. Memoirs of an Epicurean. United States, Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1942.

Sedgwick, Henry Dwight. The Art of Happiness: Or, The Teachings of Epicurus. United States, Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1933.

Sedley, D. (2018), ‘Epicurean Theories of Knowledge: From Hermarchus to Lucretius and Philodemus

Shorey, Paul. Platonism, Ancient and Modern. United States, University of California Press, 1938.

Solli, Audun. An Unconventional History of Western Philosophy: Conversations Between Men and Women Philosophers. United States, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2009.

Spink, J. S.. French Free-Thought from Gassendi to Voltaire. United Kingdom, Bloomsbury Publishing, 2013.

Stace, et al. P. Papinius Statius, Silvae Book II: A Commentary. Netherlands, E.J. Brill, 1984.

Stanton, Domna C.. The Dynamics of Gender in Early Modern France: Women Writ, Women Writing. United Kingdom, Taylor & Francis, 2016.

Taylor, Erana Jae. Tsuji Jun: Japanese Dadaist, Anarchist, Philosopher, Monk. Enemy Combatant Publications, 2018.

Taylor, Henry. Autobiography of Henry Taylor. 1800-1875. United Kingdom, Longmans, Green and Company, 1885.

The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism. Russia, Cambridge University Press, 2009.

The Philosophizing Muse: The Influence of Greek Philosophy on Roman Poetry. United Kingdom, Cambridge Scholars Publisher, 2014.

Thinkers and Theories in Ethics. United States, Britannica Educational Pub., 2011.

Trumbach, Randolph. Sex and the Gender Revolution. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1998.

Tsouna-McKirahan, Voula, and Tsouna, Voula. The Ethics of Philodemus. Kiribati, Clarendon Press, 2007.

Vallance, J. T. The lost theory of Asclepiades of Bithynia. United Kingdom, Claredon Press, 1990.

Wallace, William. Epicureanism. United Kingdom, Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge, 1880.

Wilson, Catherine. Epicureanism: A Very Short Introduction. United Kingdom, University of Oxford, 2015

Yona, Sergio. Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire. United Kingdom, Oxford University Press, 2018.

Laughter as a Philosophical Practice

At the same time we must laugh and philosophize, do our household duties and manage our business, and never cease proclaiming the sayings of the true philosophy. – ES 41

Recently, a fellow SoFE member cited this saying to me, stressing that we MUST laugh, that it is an order, not a suggestion. This was in the context of a discussion on how, of all the attributes that a person needs in order to be able to profit from the study of philosophy, the person’s attitude or disposition (diathesis) is surprisingly more important than many other attributes. Yes, we want students of philosophy to be knowledgeable, and ideally happy, but even if they’re beginners with little more to offer, so long as they have a good disposition, slowly they will profit, learn, and become happy with the use of the tools that philosophy gives. If they have the wrong attitude, they will not profit.

Epicurus expressed this by saying that his Doctrines are not for everyone, but only for those who are “armed for happiness“. We are left to determine what it means to be armed, or prepared, for happiness. It seems to imply that a certain attitudinal training, or the cultivation of healthy and happy dispositions, is required. Later Epicureans (like Philodemus of Gadara and Diogenes of Oenoanda) also stressed the importance of diathesis in their writing, with Diogenes stressing that our dispositions are under our control.

But why must laughter be part of our practice of philosophy, and part of our art of living (techné biou)? Laughter is a concrete instance of pleasure, manifesting and asserting itself as sound vibration, as tremor and movement in the body and mind, making itself concrete. Some specific object of our attention produces a concrete joy. Our disposition or attitude can not be known by others, except if it produces concrete instances of pleasure, the signs of which are laughter and other behaviors. If we cultivate a certain disposition, if we are armed for happiness, there have to be “fruits”, signs, observable expressions of this in our behavior: our willingness to laugh at ourselves and at events, an ease of enjoying simple things, our gratefulness, etc.

Furthermore, the cultivation of a sunny disposition creates a positive feedback loop or virtuous cycle. Studies suggest that just as people who are always angry, look mad and ugly, similarly people who are happy and confident are also more attractive. Laughing makes us radiant, and is contagious.

The Laughing Philosophers

It makes sense that laughter should be one of the basic philosophical exercises in our school. Epicureans fall within the lineage of the laughing philosophers, which begins with Democritus–the inventor of atomism–who was called the “laughing philosopher” because he made cheerfulness his cardinal virtue, and because he laughed frequently at the folly of human nature. I delve a bit more into the relation between laughter and materialism in this essay about the history and utility of comedy.

Friederich Nietzsche, in Thus Spake Zarathustra, elevated laughter to the status of a holy practice.

Laughter is holy. All good things laugh. – Nietzsche

But he went further. You see, Nietzsche specifically chose the prophet Asho Zartosht as the mouthpiece for his own philosophy for a reason. (I am using the Persian name in order to differentiate the historical Zartosht from Nietzsche’s Zarathustra). It may surprise some that the Iranian prophet Zarathustra himself was a laughing philosopher: there’s a legend that says that he was born laughing. The first monotheistic prophet appears at the dawn of recorded history, is pre-Abrahamic, and therefore not yet tainted with the asceticism or with the Platonist hatred for the world that we would see in later “prophets”, and which would find its most sick expression in figures like the “prophet” Mani–who blended Platonism, Christianity and Zoroastrianism into what seems like a mishmash of world-hating ideas.

In contrast, the Persian philosopher and moral reformer Zartosht was not at all a world-denying philosopher. He said: “Happy is the one who brings happiness to others“, and one of the main mantras of Zorostrianism (the Ashem Vohu) equates Asha (righteousness, truth, or justice) with Ushta (pleasure, happiness). Ushta (happiness), then, became the sign that righteousness was being properly honored and practiced in the world. This reminds us a bit of Epicurus’ Principal Doctrine 5.

Nietzsche chose Zartosht as his spokesperson because he considered him a worthy philosophical enemy, one whose ideas could still be reformed and useful. Like Zartosht, Nietzsche conceived of a cosmic battle–but not between “good” and “evil”. Nietzsche’s Neo-Zoroastrian battle is a battle between Laughter (light, lightening up, dancing, leaping) and the Spirit of Gravity, which pulls us down and represents a regressive instinct. Nietzsche’s “Ahriman” (“evil” “spirit”) is recognized for its inability to laugh.

I should only believe in a God that would know how to dance. And when I saw my devil, I found him serious, thorough, profound, solemn: he was the spirit of gravity. Through him all things fall. Not by wrath, but by laughter, do we slay. Come, let us slay the spirit of gravity!

When Asho Zartosht spoke of “spirits”, the word he actually used was Mainyu. This translates into “mentality”, or “disposition”. Spenta Mainyu translates as something like “Progressive, or Constructive Mentality”, while Anghra Mainyu is “Regressive, or Harmful Mentality”. Another name for Anghra is Aka Mainyu (the “Sick, or Evil, Mindset”). Asho Zartosht taught that these two basic dispositions are “twins” congenital to human nature, born together in our souls, and the more we “feed” them, or “sacrifice” to each, the more they strengthen. He taught that we co-create our worlds through these two basic mentalities by our choices and rejections of concrete thoughts, words, and deeds.

However, as his philosophy evolved within the context of its religious trappings, these “Mainyu” became mystified. Spenta Mainyu evolved into the Christian Holy Spirit, while Anghra Mainyu evolved into the Devil. People adopted an obscure and superstitious interpretation of them, moving away from the original psychological insights.

As Epicureans, we reject the mythologized and absolute understanding of Regressive and Progressive Mentality as two cosmic forces. Instead, we may look at our choices and rejections in terms of what type of mentality is behind each impulse we feel, perhaps by naming them “the better” and “the worse” mentalities at the time–since our cosmological model is not absolute, but always relative or relational. This would help us to practice paying closer attention to our choices and avoidances, and to our dispositions, cultivating the healthier ones (which are advantageous for our happiness), and rejecting the sick ones (which are harmful to our happiness).

Laughter as a Practice

I’ve written an introductory set of considerations for how to practice Epicurean Saying 41, which is the most overt call for laughter as a philosophical practice in our extant Epicurean writings.

Laughter yoga has demonstrated effectiveness in reducing pain and is used in therapeutic settings with cancer patientsUltimately, it is up to us as individuals to choose to develop a regular practice of laughter, and to incorporate it in concrete ways into our hedonic regimen. This can be as simple as a weekly gathering of family or friends, a funny movie, or a formal session of laughter practice.

Life is not serious: only graveyards are serious“. – Atheist Indian guru Osho, in his sermon against the repression of laughter

Further Reading:

6 Reasons Why Laughter Is the Best Medicine 

Short Laughter Yoga Ted Talk

In Memory of a Laughing Philosopher

Comedy as an Ideological Weapon

Nature has no masters: Lucretius, Epicurus, and Effortless Action

“Nature does nothing, and yet nothing remains unaccomplished.” – Tao Te Ching, with “nature” replacing the Tao

Wu Wei (Doing Nothing 無爲) is a key concept in Taoism and in Chinese philosophy. Encyclopaedia Britannica defines wu wei as:

the practice of taking no action that is not in accord with the natural course of the universe.

Which reminds us of the Epicurean insistence of living in accordance with nature, defined as living pleasantly (rationally and pragmatically following the pleasure impulse and evading the pain signals). According to The School of Life,

It means being at peace while engaged in the most frenetic tasks so that one can carry these out with maximum skill and efficiency. Something of the meaning of wu wei is captured when we talk of being ‘in the zone’ – at one with what we are doing, in a state of profound concentration and flow.

… so that it seems that wu wei is a way of acting that does not interrupt the natural flows, including those of sentience and attention. Wu wei also is associated with the enjoyment of things without clinging or yearning. A metaphor for this is the bee which goes from flower to flower, enjoying the nectar freely, and moving on. We also see the logic of wu wei in the Lathe biosas (Live unknown) teaching, and in the focus on natural and necessary pleasures which are easy to get.

In Taoism, the focus is less on accepting that which you cannot change (as the Stoics do), and more on acting efficiently and effortlessly. A clear, non-mystical understanding of wu wei helps to remind us of the wisdom of choosing our battles, and choosing the most efficient and opportune moments and circumstances in which to act. According to this essay by LR:

A better way to think of it, however, is as a paradoxical “Action of non-action.”

This is very problematic for us, since Epicurean philosophy frowns upon unclear speech. But wu wei is far from a mystical and unpragmatic idea. It’s applied effectively in many fields, including business, politics, and martial arts.

Over 20 years ago, when I studied tai chi under an instructor who had been trained in China, he explained wu wei to me by teaching me that in addition to evading or dodging a blow and allowing the opponent to tire and hurt himself in various ways, we can also use the momentum from our own bodies and the strength of our legs when we counter-attack. This, too, is wu-wei, and it’s not just effortless: it’s efficient. He struck a blow once from a position of being steady on his feet, and then another one with a dancing motion, using his legs to add momentum to the blow. This second blow was, naturally, much stronger than the first (because he used momentum and I felt the weight of his whole body), and it pushed me back. He then said: “THAT is wu wei”. I was planning to move to Chicago in a month, so my tai chi classes were brief, but I always remembered this encounter, and the sense that the Sensei was on to something.

Sometimes wu wei is about the use of observable factors over which we may have no control, and sometimes it’s about the employment of the few other factors over which we DO have control, but that when applied at the right moment and in the right way, create much more effective ways of acting in the world thanks to the assistance of nature. According to this essay,

Another example of Wu Wei is the cutting of wood. If you go against the way the tree grew, the wood is difficult to cut. The wood, however, splits easily if you cut against the grain. When sawing wood, many people are in a great hurry to power through the block and do not realize they are splintering the back edge. Instead, a skilled carpenter will let the saw do the work, patiently allowing the blade to glide across the wood without causing any splinters or tiring themselves out.

Wu wei reminds me of the way in which sleep assists in neuroplasticity and in the process of memorizing and learning. Before we are able to perform a task thoroughly and subconsciously, without even thinking about it, many neural connections must happen in our brains, and these neurons do their repair work at night while we sleep. We do our active memorizing and learning while we’re awake, but (arguably) the most important work happens at night, when the brain really goes to work on learning. We must give up the power over the tasks or information that we’re learning, and allow the brain to rest, in order to learn. Without this effortless aspect of the process, learning does not happen. According to this study:

… during sleep, the brain must also stabilize key synapses to prevent what was learned the previous day from being eliminated by new learning experiences…

… the REM stage may make learning before sleep more resilient to interference from subsequent learning.

Unlike non-REM sleep, the sharp fall in plasticity during REM sleep was only seen among the volunteers with a task to learn.

This suggests that the stabilization that occurred during REM sleep was focused exclusively on synapses involved in learning this task.

Darwinian natural selection provides us another example where, without much effort on the part of sentient beings, things continue along their course, and even evolve into a magnificent variety of lifeforms. If some mutation, or some instinctive behavior, results in advantage for a creature, then that creature is more likely to survive and pass on their genes while others do not. Over time, only the better adapted creatures will remain. Like water, nature in all things takes the path of least resistance.

Another application of wu wei happens in communities where engineers of the beaver species have interfered with human communal engineering decisions. Scientists have figured out that if you play the soundtrack of running water, upon hearing it, beavers will begin to build dams by instinct. So they are using this to manipulate beaver behavior as needed. Rather than fight the critters, rather than make countless efforts, rather than be in control, humans simply need to encourage the creature to do what it’s programmed by nature to do whenever it hears running water.

We must not force Nature but persuade her. We shall persuade her if we satisfy the necessary desires and also those bodily desires that do not harm us while sternly rejecting those that are harmful. – Epicurean Saying 21

I have long considered that pleasure ethics often involves a practice of applying the same technique that we apply with the beavers, with ourselves; a practice which–in my view–requires insight, wisdom and self-compassion.

Epicurean Effortless Action

I have shared all these case studies on effortless yet efficient action in order to show that, while sometimes our instincts are triggered in vain, most of the time it does make sense to trust the wisdom of nature. A clear insight into wu wei may help us in our choices and avoidances, to more efficiently choose our efforts, and to act in a manner that is more confident, more efficient, less anxious, and yet paradoxically less in need of control. But what does Epicurean philosophy say concretely concerning effortless action? Epicurus’ Principal Doctrine 26 says:

The desires that do not bring pain when they go unfulfilled are not necessary; indeed they are easy to reject if they are hard to achieve or if they seem to produce harm.

Epicurus offers us two criteria in our choices and avoidances that justify not pursuing unnecessary pleasures: if they’re hard to achieve, or if they’re harmful, then it’s easy to dismiss them. This first criteria, of course, reminds us of wu wei (effortless action), and also the Doctrine seems to imply that it is desirable to live in such a way that our choices and avoidances tend to produce pleasures that generally require little effort.

Principal Doctrine 30, on the other hand, offers us two criteria to classify some natural desires as arising from groundless opinion:

Among natural desires, those that do not bring pain when unfulfilled and that require intense exertion arise from groundless opinion; and such desires fail to be stamped out not by nature but because of the groundless opinions of humankind.

Notice the second criterion involves the desires that require intense exertion. Here again, we find an ethics of effortless (or low effort) action in Epicurean Doctrines, tied to the accusation that the justifications for exertion involve faulty thinking not based on the study of nature.

We see in Epicurean pleasure calculus and in wu-wei a tendency to affirm nature, as well as some distrust of culture or artifice. We also see a tendency to follow the path of least resistance. But when we read Lucretius and consider Epicurean physics, wu wei comes into a different relief.

Effortless Action and Epicurean Atheology

The fullness of the pragmatic repercussions of these considerations, ordinary and seemingly unrelated as they are, is carried to its conclusion by Lucretius. This is the beauty of Epicurean philosophy: it rationally and pragmatically weaves cosmology, physics, epistemology, and ethics into a single, coherent tapestry.

If you grasp these points well and hold to them,
you will see at once that nature is free,
liberated from her proud possessors,
doing all things on her own initiative,
without divinities playing any part.

Lucretius, On the nature of things, Book II

… which, of course, has repercussions for how we should live our lives (the ethics). The gods do not govern, create, or interrupt the workings of nature. Therefore, even if we attribute an artistic-aesthetic or ethical role to the gods in our lives, we need not worry about appeasing them. This, too, allows us to engage in more effective action in our environment, as it protects us from the degrading superstitions of the mobs who are forever appeasing gods out of unwarranted shame or fear.

Without gods managing everything, nature is free. Nature acts according to its own laws and cycles, which are unconscious and impersonal, and it is by prudently acting in accordance with (or not against) these cycles and laws that we act most efficiently.

Further reading:

Contemplations on Tao

The Taoist Hedonism of Yang Chu

How Do We Memorialize our Fallen?

The noble man is chiefly concerned with wisdom and friendship; of these, the former is a mortal good, the latter an immortal one. – Vatican Saying 78

"Of all the things that wisdom provides for a happy life, by far the greatest is friendship." - from Jesús' instagram feed

“Of all the things that wisdom provides for a happy life, by far the greatest is friendship.” – from Jesús’ instagram feed

By now some of you will be aware that our friend Jesús (SoFE member and one of the admins of the Spanish SoFE group) passed away around the 20th in a bicycle accident. Jesús was a professor of political science in Venezuela. His way of dealing with all the things that have been happening in his country was through the frequent use of comedy and cynical commentary. He was instrumental in the last two years in translating many writings for the Spanish page of the Society of Friends of Epicurus. He often carried a copy of Epicurus’ Doctrines with him for study and remembrance, and some of his friends and/or students reported that he had been sharing the Epicurean Gospel with them. He was a very smart and sincere Epicurean, and thanks to his steady participation in our monthly zoom meetings, our Eikas had become a bilingual event. We’re going to miss him.

This is not the first time we lose an Epicurean in our circle. It leads us to philosophize about these questions: How do we properly mourn our Epicurean Friends? How can we remain considerate and respectful of family members who do not share our values, while also properly honoring the memory and the sincerely-held beliefs of our Friend? What funerary and/or memorial traditions will we implement? Principal Doctrine 40 reminds us that we should “not grieve the early death of the departed, as though it called for pity.” The practice recommended for remembering our fallen is known as “pleasant remembrance”. Initially, this may be difficult to achieve, but over time we should fill the hole in the world left by the departed with pleasant memories.

The celebration of Eikas on the Twentieth of every month was originally a memorial service honoring the Epicureans who have passed, and furnishes a great opportunity to pour our libations and remember him. Therefore, we did a private memorial toast to the memory of Jesús during our Eikas zoom meeting this weekend.

The Reemergence of the Roman Epicurean Burial Tradition

Maybe this may teach us something about the utility, in times like these, of having healthy ecumenical relations with Christians. When we learned of Jesús death, we also learned (from his brother) that his mother would probably not allow a non-Christian funeral. After all, she named him after Jesus Christ and is very Catholic (and devastated). One of the first things we are learning from this is that funerals are for the living. They help bring closure and comfort to the survivors. As Philodemus the Guide reminded us in his scroll On Death, the person who has died is not there, and does not benefit in any way whatsoever from funeral rites.

Therefore, we must consider that, for the Christian survivors, it is normal that they will want to remember him according to the rites and traditions of Christianity, and that for the Epicurean survivors, it is normal that we will want to remember him according to our own traditions. For this reason, after speaking to his brother, it was important for us to respect the Christian family’s ways of mourning, and we figured we would simply mourn and remember Jesús in our own way privately, but our friend Alan did share imagery inspired by the inscriptions that were used by Roman Epicureans on their tombs with some of the friends and students of Jesús, and some of them expressed that it would be a nice gesture to honor his sincerely-held Epicurean beliefs in some way. After all, his beliefs were a big part of what made him who he was, and part of why people loved him.



He was loved by many in his community. One of his friends said: “He will be immortal to us“.

So we were very pleasantly surprised when, after the funeral, we received an image of Jesús Guevara’s tomb. Someone who saw our post (perhaps one of his students?) had traced the image that our friend Alan had made to memorialize him over the fresh cement on his tomb. As you can see, it’s very crude, but it’s an authentic expression of the resurgence of Epicurean culture in the 21st Century in a part of the world that is deeply Catholic … and (we must acknowledge) it’s also a token of comfort, solidarity, and compassion on the part of people who are (in all likelihood) Christians, but who respect us enough and have enough compassion, kindness, and tolerance, that they prefer to honor the sincerely-held beliefs of our fallen rather than erase them, or sugar-coat them. For this, we are deeply thankful.

We only get one life, it’s very short, and sometimes we don’t get a chance to articulate our love for each other. If Jesús was still here, I’d just want to say thank you, I love you, and we will not forget you. I invite my readers to take the time to call your friends that you haven’t seen in a while–for (as the Havamal says) “a path that is neglected, slowly fills with weeds”. Peace and Safety.

Summary and Review of “The Compass of Pleasure”, a book that explores the neuroscience of pleasure

“Philosophers like the Epicureans, St. Augustine, and Nietzsche have tried to analyze and comprehend this elemental fact of our experience, but it is only recently that we have been able to study it empirically, thanks to remarkable advancements in neuroscience. In The Compass of Pleasure, David J. Linden, explains the recent research that has enabled us to understand how the brain’s pleasure circuits are engaged by our vices and, surprisingly, our virtues.”

– Dust jacket front blurb from The Compass of Pleasure: How Our Brains Make Fatty Foods, Orgasm, Exercise, Marijuana, Generosity, Vodka, Learning, and Gambling Feel So Good

I am coming up on approximately my first year since deciding to go deep into the study of Epicurean philosophy. In that time, I have learned a lot about the history of the development of pleasure ethics, from Plato’s Philebus, to Aristippus and the Cyrenaics, through to Epicurus’ more nuanced theory. However, I think that since we are living in the age of modern science, it could be useful for us to draw on the recent knowledge coming from the field of experimental neuroscience to inform and shape our understanding of pleasure ethics. It could be that modern science confirms, rejects, or at least further contextualizes the principles that were reasoned by the ancients but which could not be explored empirically until only recently. That thinking is what led to my review of this book.

The prologue to the book opens with an amusing story recounting a time when the author went travelling in Thailand. When he boarded one of the three-wheeled motorcycle taxis, the driver asked him essentially ‘what’s your pleasure?’, and proceeded to offer him a litany of contraband and illicit sexual opportunities. This triggered in his mind the question of why it is that we are such ‘dopamine fiends’, or why we go looking for pleasures of all varieties.

“We humans have a complicated and ambivalent relationship to pleasure, which we spend an enormous amount of time and resources pursuing. A key motivator of our lives, pleasure is central to learning, for we must find things like food, water, and sex rewarding in order to survive and pass our genetic material to the next generation. Certain forms of pleasure are accorded special status. Many of our most important rituals involving prayer, music, dance, and meditation produce a kind of transcendent pleasure that has become deeply ingrained in human cultural practice.”

Chapter 1: “Mashing the Pleasure Button”

This first chapter is an extended history lesson about past efforts to experiment (occasionally highly unethically by modern standards) with pleasure stimulation in animals and humans. He recounts the experiments by Hebb, Olds, and Milner starting in 1953, which involved implanting electrodes in the brains of rats and then sending electrical stimulation to specific brain regions when the rat pressed the lever. What they found was that the rats would over time become trained to seek the lever and be stimulated, and, dramatically, that the rats would furiously press the lever as many as thousands of times per hour to satisfy their fixation. They would choose the electrostimulation over food, over water, over sex, over parenting their offspring, to the point of death.

Eventually by 1972, these sorts of experiments were tried on humans, with the highly unethical goal of “bring[ing] about heterosexual behavior in a fixed, overt homosexual male.” The patient B-19 was hooked up with electrodes implanted directly at nine sites in his brain. When he was given the freedom to regulate his own stimulation, he would mash the button “like an eight-year-old playing Donkey Kong”. The author writes:

“This study is morally repugnant on many different levels — the profound arrogance of attempting to “correct” someone’s sexual orientation, the medical risk of unjustified brain surgery, the gross violations of privacy and human dignity. Fortunately, homosexual conversion therapy with brain surgery and pleasure center stimulation was soon abandoned.

Stepping back a bit, what we are left with, from this and a handful of other studies, is an appreciation of the immense power of direct electrical stimulation of the brain’s pleasure circuitry to influence human behavior, at least in the near term.”

He then gives an account of the underlying neuroscience of pleasure, which originates with signaling from neurons stemming from the ‘ventral tegmental area’ (VTA) in the brain. These electrical impulses move along the fibrous axons until they arrive at terminals. When they reach the terminals, the neurotransmitter dopamine is released from its stores in the terminal into the surrounding space, called the synaptic cleft. The dopamine then binds onto the target neuron’s dopamine receptors, and those which do not bind are then returned to the transmitting terminal in a process called ‘reuptake’ and are recycled for later use.

The molecules associated with certain drugs are able to prevent this reuptake process, which allows the stream of dopamine to cross the cleft more efficiently, and explains why these drugs are experienced as intensely euphoric and pleasurable. The author writes that the central insight of these diagrams is that:

“Experiences that cause the dopamine-containing neurons of the VTA to be active and thereby release dopamine in their targets (the nucleus accumbens, the prefrontal cortex, the dorsal striatum, and the amygdala) will be felt as pleasurable, and the sensory cues and actions that preceded and overlapped with those pleasurable experiences will be remembered and associated with positive feelings.”

These experiences remind me of what Epicurus refers to as kinetic pleasures, or the pleasures of variation and ‘motion’. Such pleasures include any of those that arise after some stimulus has impinged upon our senses, such as hearing a string quartet, licking an ice cream cone, petting a fluffy animal, gazing up at beautiful architecture, or smelling a lovely perfume. However, they are not limited to just those bodily pleasures that affect our senses, but also the mental pleasures such as remembering or anticipating pleasant experiences. These also have the power to trigger our dopamine response.

Chapter 2: “Stoned Again”

This chapter is about the different kinds of drugs and why we become addicted to them:

“All cultures use drugs that influence the brain. They range from mild stimulants like caffeine to drugs with potent euphoric effects, like morphine. Some carry a high risk of addition, some do not. Some alter perception, others mood, and some affect both. A few can kill when used to excess. The specific attitudes and laws relating to psychoactive drug use vary widely among cultures. . . “

He gives a number of historical and cross-cultural examples of drug use to illustrate his point. The first story used to illustrate the timelessness of human drug addiction is the (hitherto unknown to me but humorously surprising) case of the Stoic Emperor Marcus Aurelius’ addiction to opium:

“Perhaps it was easier to be a Stoic while stoned: The emperor was a notorious opium user, starting each day, even while on military campaigns, by downing a nubbin of the stuff dissolved in his morning cup of wine. Writings by Galen suggest that Marcus Aurelius was indeed an addict, and his accounts of the emperor’s brief periods without opium, as occurred during a campaign on the Danube, provide an accurate description of the symptoms of opiate withdrawal.”

Another interesting example of a drug used that is non-addictive and non-pleasure activating is DMT (or ayahuasca), administered in shamanic rituals by the tribes of the Amazon rainforest, which has the power to induce horrifying images in the mind (but with the therapeutic aim of overcoming these fears).

He distinguishes between those drugs that do light up our pleasure center in the brain and those that do not. As it turns out:

“Those psychoactive drugs that strongly activate the dopamine-using medial forebrain pleasure circuit (like heroin, cocaine, and amphetamines) are the very ones that carry a substantial risk of addiction, while the drugs that weakly activate the pleasure circuit (like alcohol and cannabis) carry a smaller risk of addiction. Drugs that don’t activate the pleasure circuit at all (like LSD, mescaline, benzodiazepines, and SSRI antidepressants) carry little or no risk of addition. This pleasure gradient also correlates strongly with the willingness of animals to work for these drugs.”

He also explains why only mildly-euphoric drugs like nicotine, taken in small but frequent doses, tend to be more addictive than infrequently used highly-euphoric drugs like injected heroin. It boils down to the user’s desire to achieve a comparable level of pleasure: since cigarettes are only mildly pleasant, it takes more of them to achieve a comparable dopamine hit, and the repetition of continuously exposing one’s brain to the stimulus creates dependency. He defines drug addiction as “persistent, compulsive drug use in the face of increasingly negative life consequences” and argues that addiction should be treated as a medical issue:

“When we say that addiction is a disease, aren’t we just letting addicts off the hook for their antisocial choices and behaviors? Not at all. A disease model of addiction holds that the development of addiction is not the addict’s responsibility. However, crucially, recovery from addiction is.”

From the Epicurean point of view, careful attention needs to be paid to the enjoyment of certain psychoactive drugs, and the information in this chapter is relevant to making prudent and informed decisions using the method of hedonic calculus. Additionally, we should look sympathetically towards those who are hooked on substances, because the path to recovery is arduous.

Chapter 3: “Feed Me”

This subject of this chapter is: ‘Why do we enjoy eating, how is eating regulated in the brain, and why do some people struggle with eating habits?’

The first task is to dispense with the myth of blood glucose as the primary trigger for the onset of feeding. The author says that “eating is biochemically induced only in cases of severe starvation,” and that under normal circumstances, there are other drivers of food regulation. This reminds me of a quote from Porphyry:

“Do not think it unnatural that when the flesh cries out for anything, the soul should cry out too. The cry of the flesh is, “Let me not hunger, or thirst, or shiver,” and it’s hard for the soul to restrain these desires. And while it is difficult for the soul to prevent these things, it is dangerous to neglect nature which daily proclaims self-sufficiency to the soul via the flesh which is intimately bonded to it.”

– Porphyry, Letter to Marcella

Addressing the last question first, the author explains how one contributor towards obesity is a deficiency in the hormone leptin. Leptin is secreted by fat cells that helps to regulate appetite and energy expenditure in the brain. When less fat cells are present, less leptin circulates in the body, which causes the desire for more food and less energy expenditure, resulting in weight gain. On the other hand, if there are an excess of fat cells present, more leptin in the blood is registered and so feeding is suppressed and metabolism and activity are increased to burn more energy.

“While the leptin homeostatic system explains how the brain can receive information about long-term changes in weight as indicated by body fat, it doesn’t account for the short-term regulation of appetite.”

In the short term, feeding is regulated by the feeding control circuit, taking place in the hypothalamus. There are two competing hormones, CRH which signals for hunger and orexin which signals for satiety. These hormones are in competition with one another. He likens the competition between these two signals to “an old-fashioned bathtub with separate hot and cold water taps: the temperature of the bath is then determined by the relative flow of hot and cold water.”

Okay, but this all sounds very deterministic, as if we were just biological machines responding to chemical circumstances and states in our brain. Don’t we have free will in all matters? This is what Linden has to say on that:

“The idea that eating is primarily a conscious and voluntary behavior is deeply rooted in our culture. We humans are invested in the notion that we have free will in all things. We want to believe that weight can be controlled by volition alone. Why can’t that fat guy just eat less and exercise more? He just lacks willpower, right? Not at all. Our homeostatic feeding control circuits make it very hard to lose a lot of weight and keep it off.”

We should not be too hard on ourselves or others who are struggling with diet and weight management. We can try to train ourselves to rely on less food, but not all people will be capable of doing so without medical intervention.

However, the first question has still not been addressed. Does the pleasure circuit activate during the naturally pleasant act of eating? “The answer is clearly yes,” says Linden. Eating releases a surge of dopamine:

“These studies revealed not only that eating was associated with dopamine release, but also that the degree of dopamine release could be used to predict how pleasurable the subject rated the experience of eating. Different foods produced different levels of dopamine release, a finding that correlated with the reported pleasures of eating. . . . Also, as hungry subjects continued to eat and became sated, the amount of dopamine released in the dorsal striatum was reduced. Not surprising: The first bites of a meal give the most pleasure when you’re hungry.”

This means that certain foods are more pleasant to eat than others, and the amount of pleasure experienced diminishes as eating proceeds, with that first bite being the most delicious. However, after the eating has occurred, it would seem that the feeling of satiety is the same regardless of what food was consumed. This reminds me of some lines from the Letter to Menoeceus:

“Just as he does not choose the greatest amount of food but the most pleasing food, so he savors not the longest time but the span of time that brings the greatest joy.”

“So simple flavors bring just as much pleasure as a fancy diet if all pain from true need has been removed, and bread and water give the highest pleasure when someone in need partakes of them.”

Later in the chapter he talks about how stress can lead to overeating. It does so by causing a complicated cascade of hormonal signaling that results in corticosterone passing into the brain, triggering the feeling of stress that leads to overeating. One possible remedy to this is to try out “behavioral strategies for stress reduction, like meditation or exercise, [that] can reduce the amplitude of stress hormone surges and are thereby effective in reducing stress-triggered overeating.”

So there is a utility to practices like meditation, which can help regulate our stress levels. An Epicurean meditation can consist of contemplation of the Epicurean gods or on the meaning of the Kyriai Doxai.

Chapter 4: “Your Sexy Brain”

“When I’ve spoken about our human behavior in regard to drugs or food, I’ve indicated that we’re basically the same as other mammals. While we have a bigger neocortex than a mouse or a monkey, and therefore a greater ability to counteract our subconscious drives with cognitive control, at the root our responses to food and psychoactive drugs are the same as those of our distant mammalian relatives. The same is not true of our mating system.”

This chapter looks at the experience of sex, sexual patterns, and sexual addiction (by now you might be finding a pattern in this book – he is very interested in how harmful behavioral patterns form). In humans, unlike some of the other mammals, sex is frequently recreational. Additionally, most of the other mammals are promiscuous, whereas humans tend to be monogamous. Homosexuality is another trait present in humans that can be found in animals. Looking towards our primate cousins, the author observes the following about bonobos:

“In bonobos, it seems as if homosexual behavior, in addition to providing sexual pleasure, also fulfills a social role by diffusing tension and promoting social bonding at the expense of aggression.”

So it seems that a variety of different orientations (heterosexual vs homosexual, etc.) and mating style tendencies (monogamous vs non-monogamous) can be found in the animal kingdom, as well as in humans.

Linden continues by examining the properties of sexual addiction. He regrets to observe that in our society, the sexually addicted have a low probability of seeking help due to social stigma. Sexual addiction is a very real phenomenon that has terrible consequences for not only those people who become addicted but also those people who are treated as means to the end of satisfying the addiction.

Regarding these topics, Metrodorus has this to say:

“[addressing a young man] I understand from you that your natural disposition is too much inclined toward sexual passion. Follow your inclination as you will, provided only that you neither violate the laws, disturb well-established customs, harm any one of your neighbors, injure your own body, nor waste your possessions. That you be not checked by one or more of these provisos is impossible; for a man never gets any good from sexual passion, and he is fortunate if he does not receive harm.”

Before we view this as a directive against any sort of sexuality whatsoever, we must appreciate the context in which this was written: a world without contraception, STD protection, and traditional social mores and regulations. If Metrodorus could see the context of today’s world, it is likely he would not be so hard on modern Epicureans who wish to satisfy their natural desires harmlessly. Care must be taken so as not to become sexually addicted.

Chapter 5: “Gambling and Other Modern Compulsions”

This chapter is about other miscellaneous compulsions, including a diverse range of addictions, such as addiction to the Internet, gambling, pornography, chocolate, consumerism, etc. One of the central questions he is attempting to address is why is it that abstract concepts (that are not immediately sensible) are perceived as pleasant. He presents a number of experiments to explore these matters in detail, such as experiments in reward association in monkeys. He concludes by saying that:

“This chapter has seen our ideas of the dopamine pleasure circuit extended in some provocative directions. Initially it seemed that the pleasure circuit was either naturally activated by intrinsically adaptive stimuli like food, water, or sex, or artificially engaged by drugs or stimulating electrodes placed deep within the brain. We also discussed how the development of addiction could slowly modify the structure and function of the pleasure circuit and thereby drain the pleasure out of any of these activities, replacing liking with wanting. These observations are all true, but they don’t tell the whole story.

We now know from Schultz’s monkey experiments that rapid associative learning can transform a pleasure signal into a reward prediction error signal that can guide learning to maximize future pleasure. It is likely that this same process is what enables humans to feel pleasure from arbitrary rewards like monetary gain (or even near misses in monetary gain) or winning at a video game.”

So it seems that we do have the capacity to experience mental pleasures that stem from the expectation of future reward. The Epicureans held that the pleasures of the mind can even exceed the pleasure of the flesh. The anticipation of a future pleasure can be a powerful motivator of behavior.

Chapter 6: “Virtuous Pleasures (and a Little Pain)”

This chapter is about the ‘virtuous’ pleasures – those pleasures that come with some voluntary effort but are overall good for us and our wellbeing, such as exercise, meditation, fasting, and philanthropic giving.

“Sustained physical exercise, whether it be running or swimming or cycling or some other aerobic activity, has well-known health benefits, including improvements in the function of the cardiovascular, pulmonary, and endocrine systems. Voluntary exercise is also associated with long-term improvements in mental function and is the single best thing one can do to slow the cognitive decline that accompanies normal aging. Exercise has a dramatic antidepressive effect. It blunts the brain’s response to physical and emotional stress.

Given these massive long-term benefits, it is clear that voluntary exercise is a useful component of one’s hedonic regimen. Although these activities may be strenuous in their performance, the subsequent advantages accrued are worth taking into consideration. Additionally, one may enjoy short-term benefits, such as “increased pain threshold, reduction of acute anxiety, and ‘runner’s high’, which is a short-lasting, deeply euphoric state that’s well beyond the simple relaxation or peacefulness felt by many following intense exercise.”

“Another virtuous pleasure that is culturally widespread and often linked to spiritual practice is meditation. . . .While meditation is certainly relaxing and is sometimes described as blissful, does it in fact activate the medial forebrain pleasure circuit? [One study] found a significant increase in dopamine release in the nucleus accumbens of their meditators. This result is suggestive, but it awaits both confirmation and extension to other forms of meditation.

What is clear about meditation is that it has the ability to reduce our stress, activate a large number of brain regions, and decrease the activation of other brain regions. What is still unclear is whether it triggers the release of dopamine. It is worth experimenting for yourself to see whether mediation can form a useful component of your hedonic regimen.

Can fasting also serve a role in our hedonic regimen? The staving off of eating for an increased period of time induces the body to enter a state of autophagy, whereby the body draws upon its stored resources to provide energy, hence burning fat. So fasting can help regulate body weight. Additionally, after one has fasted for a period of time, the amount of pleasure one experiences at the break of the fast may be impressive. Regarding fasting, Seneca had this to report about Epicurus:

“The great hedonist teacher Epicurus used to observe certain periods during which he would be frugal in satisfying his hunger, with the object of seeing to what extent, if at all, one thereby fell short of attaining full and complete pleasure, and whether it was worth going to much trouble to make the deficit good.  At least so he says in the letter he wrote to Polyaenus in the archonship of Charinus {308 – 307 B.C.}.  He boasts in it indeed that he is managing to feed himself for less than a half-penny, whereas Metrodorus, not yet having made such good progress, needs a whole half-penny!”

– Seneca, Letter to Lucilius

Partly through the chapter, the author dissects the claim by Jeremy Bentham that we are subjects of our masters, pleasure and pain:

“In the late eighteenth century the British philosopher Jeremy Bentham famously proclaimed,

“Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. . . . They  govern us in all we do, in all we say, in all we think: every effort we can make to throw off our subjection, will serve but to demonstrate and confirm it.”

The accumulating neurobiological evidence indicates that Bentham was only half correct. Pleasure is indeed one compass of our mental function, guiding us toward both virtues and vices, and pain is another. However, we now have reason to believe that they are not two ends of a continuum. The opposite of pleasure isn’t pain; rather, just as the opposite of love is not hate but indifference, the opposite of pleasure is not pain but ennui — a lack of interest in sensation and experience.

You don’t have to be a sadomasochistic sex enthusiast to know that pleasure and pain can be felt simultaneously: Recall Boecker’s aching but blissful long-distance runners, or women in childbirth. In the lexicon of cognitive neuroscience, both pleasure and pain indicate salience, that is, experience that is potentially important and thereby deserving of attention. Emotion is the currency of salience, and both positive emotions — like euphoria and love — and negative emotions — like fear, anger, and disgust — signal events that we must not ignore.”

So he contends that the opposite of pleasure is not pain but rather ennui, in this sense interpretable as a lack of excitement, and that pleasure and pain are both salient experiences, or having the quality of being important or prominent to respond to. For example, the sensation of pain in animals is often triggered by nociception, which is the response to exposure to noxious stimuli. In order to preserve the integrity of the endangered body part, the animal recoils and avoids the stimuli and experiences a feeling of pain.

Chapter 7: “The Future of Pleasure”

This chapter is about the future of pleasure as neuroscience and nanoscience research progress. The author is skeptical about the near term feasibility of nanobots invading our brains and simulating perfect-fidelity sensory experiences and virtual realities. He departs from the optimism of futurists like Ray Kurzweil, who think that the biotechnological revolution is coming in the next decade or two. The central disagreement is about the pace of the neuroscience research, which he argues will drag on in a linear fashion in spite of the fact that technological capability will continue to advance at an exponential pace.

He concludes the book with the following passage:

“In the end, however, thinking about the future of pleasure comes down to the individual. If pleasure is ubiquitous, what will happen to our human “superpower” of being able to associate pleasure with abstract ideas? Will it be washed away in a sea of background noise? If pleasure is everywhere, will uniquely human goals still exist? When pleasure is ubiquitous, what will we desire?

Conclusion

This has been a very brief and surface level summary of this book. I give it a strong recommendation (I think a copy can be picked up cheaply on ebay or abebooks, if not for free at the library), or from amazon. I think that it contains many positive and practical takeaways for the practitioner of Epicurean philosophy, or of pleasure/hedonic/utilitarian ethics in general.


David J. Linden, PhD, is a highly influential American professor of neuroscience at Johns Hopkins University and editor in chief of The Journal of Neurophysiology. He has written some popular books for the scientifically-interested lay audience, including in addition to this one, The Accidental Mind: How Brain Evolution Has Given Us Love, Memory, Dreams, and God and Touch: The Science of the Hand, Heart, and Mind.

This review summary was written by Friend Harmonious with editorial feedback from Guide Hiram.

Further Reading:

The Compass of Pleasure

Passages on the Soul, from Epicurus’ Epistle to Herodotus

The Letter to Herodotus is available here in its entirety. A commentary on the Epicurean Doctrine of the Psyche is here.

Also read: Some thoughts on the soul

Our canon is that direct observation by sense and direct apprehension by the mind are alone invariably true.

63

“Next, keeping in view our perceptions and feelings (for so shall we have the surest grounds for belief), we must recognize generally that the soul is a corporeal thing, composed of fine particles, dispersed all over the frame, most nearly resembling wind with an admixture of heat, in some respects like wind, in others like heat. But, again, there is the third part which exceeds the other two in the fineness of its particles and thereby keeps in closer touch with the rest of the frame. And this is shown by the mental faculties and feelings, by the ease with which the mind moves, and by thoughts, and by all those things the loss of which causes death. Further, we must keep in mind that soul has the greatest share in causing sensation.

64

Still, it would not have had sensation, had it not been somehow confined within the rest of the frame. But the rest of the frame, though it provides this indispensable condition for the soul, itself also has a share, derived from the soul, of the said quality; and yet does not possess all the qualities of soul. Hence on the departure of the soul it loses sentience. For it had not this power in itself; but something else, congenital with the body, supplied it to body: which other thing, through the potentiality actualized in it by means of motion, at once acquired for itself a quality of sentience, and, in virtue of the neighbourhood and interconnexion between them, imparted it (as I said) to the body also.

65

“Hence, so long as the soul is in the body, it never loses sentience through the removal of some other part. The containing sheath may be dislocated in whole or in part, and portions of the soul may thereby be lost; yet in spite of this the soul, if it manage to survive, will have sentience. But the rest of the frame, whether the whole of it survives or only a part, no longer has sensation, when once those atoms have departed, which, however few in number, are required to constitute the nature of soul. Moreover, when the whole frame is broken up, the soul is scattered and has no longer the same powers as before, nor the same motions; hence it does not possess sentience either.

66

“For we cannot think of it as sentient, except it be in this composite whole and moving with these movements; nor can we so think of it when the sheaths which enclose and surround it are not the same as those in which the soul is now located and in which it performs these movements. 

67

“There is the further point to be considered, what the incorporeal can be, if, I mean, according to current usage the term is applied to what can be conceived as self-existent. But it is impossible to conceive anything that is incorporeal as self-existent except empty space. And empty space cannot itself either act or be acted upon, but simply allows a body to move through it. Hence those who call soul incorporeal speak foolishly. For if it were so, it could neither act nor be acted upon. But, as it is, both these properties, you see, plainly belong to soul.

68

“If, then, we bring all these arguments concerning soul to the criterion of our feelings and perceptions, and if we keep in mind the proposition stated at the outset, we shall see that the subject has been adequately comprehended in outline: which will enable us to determine the details with accuracy and confidence.

Further Reading:

A Concrete Self

Some thoughts on the soul

 

On the Occasion of the Birth of the Hegemon

For many years, we have had difficulty establishing with certainty the date of the birth of Epicurus. This is because the Attic calendar–whose months were mentioned in Epicurus’ Last Will and Testament–was not widely used. It was very much a local calendar, and was lunisolar, which adds great confusion for us who are used to our (solar) Gregorian calendar. The Birth of the Hegemon should naturally be our biggest holiday, our equivalent of Christmas, Mawlid, or Buddha Purnima, so at the SoFE we decided it was time to fix the date and to start developing traditions around the holiday of the Birth of the Hegemon.

The Lunisolar Calendar Discussion

We looked into various possible solutions. I considered adapting the Attic calendar into a simplified lunisolar calendar, abandoning the traditional and difficult-to-pronounce Greek month names and replacing them with the generic “First Moon”, “Second Moon”, etc. as names for our months. Some years would have twelve moons, and others would have thirteen. According to Wikipedia:

The year was meant to begin with the first sighting of the new moon after the summer solstice.

This would have been easy enough, as there are plenty of lunar calendars online we can consult. In his final will, Epicurus describesthe customary celebration of my birthday on the tenth day of Gamelion in each year“. Gamelion was the seventh month, which typically falls in January-February. But in 2020-2021, the summer solstice coincided with the new moon, and therefore the lunisolar months came very early. According to space.com, there was a new moon on June 21st of 2020, which is right at the solstice, so the solstice coincided with the New (Lunisolar) Year.

If we count seven new moons from there, we will see that space.com sets the seventh new moon of year 2,361 of the Age of Epicurus as December the 14th.

Therefore, the tenth day of the seventh moon in this simplified lunisolar calendar, counting from December 14th, would have been the 23rd day of December of 2020–which would have been the Birth of the Hegemon in our simplified lunisolar calendar. However, in the ancient Attic calendar, each month began with the “first sighting of the new moon”, which in this case was probably one or two nights after the New Moon of the 14th of December of 2020. We are beginning to see how difficult it is to plan ahead for this, which creates many disadvantages.

When we say that we are in the Year of Epicurus 2,361, we calculate that from 2020 (current year in the Gregorian calendar, which begins the lunisolar cycle of 2020-2021), plus 341 (Before Common Era, the year of his birth).

When I consulted with the other members of the SoFE concerning the problem of the date of this holiday, we considered the possibility of adopting a private lunisolar calendar merely with the intention of clearly calculating the Birth of the Hegemon every year, and we had to carry out hedonic calculus between this option and sticking to our familiar Gregorian calendar for the sake of simplicity, ease, and custom. The idea of fixing the Birth of the Hegemon to the Gregorian calendar prevailed. While I am not averse to the idea of a lunisolar calendar, the utility of this is limited, since the only major lunisolar holiday we celebrate is the Birth of the Hegemon.

Also, we customarily have zoom gatherings on the Twentieth of every month (or sometimes on the most convenient date close to the Twentieth), which makes it advantageous to merge the Birth of the Hegemon and the Twentieth on its given month, and also helps us to respect and to make the best use of each other’s time.

Therefore, the Society of Friends of Epicurus has officially set the holiday of the Birth of the Hegemon to be henceforward celebrated on the 20th of February every year.

Meaning of Hegemon

Epicurus was known as the Hegemon by his disciples. We pronounce this word according to the US conventional pronunciation found here. This word is related to “hegemony”, which translates as:

 preponderant influence or authority over others. – Webster Dictionary

Other translations of the word are political, and do not apply to the ancient usage. This does not mean that he is infallible, or a prophet. He’s the founder of our School, our moral example due to his empirical thinking, clear and frank speech and clear thought, freedom from superstition and harmful beliefs, his pleasant disposition, his autarchy, his friendliness, and his kindness. He was the first Epicurean, the one whose name (and a portion of his identity) we make our own when we call ourselves Epicureans. The name Epicurus means “Friend” or “Ally”, and we know that friendship was holy to the first Epicureans, so in our Koinonia we strive to be true Friends and allies to each other.

We recognize only Epicurus of Samos as our Hegemon. His successors (diadochi) of direct lineage in the Garden of Athens were known as Scholarchs (Hermarchus, Polystratus, Zeno of Sidon, etc.) The Age of the Scholarchs lasted over five centuries. No one today can claim direct lineage, and so there are no Scholarchs today.

Under the Scholarchs, were the kath-hegetes (Guides)–people like Philodemus of Gadara, Philonides of Laodicea, Diogenes of Oenoanda, etc. In our SoFE lineage, this is the only office that we recognize as still potentially existing today.

In Celebration of the Birth of the Hegemon

Today is for remembering some of the key events in the biography and some of the key features of the character of Epicurus of Samos through poetry, declamation, and other art forms. We encourage all followers of Epicurus to write their own poems and statements in memory of the Hegemon for this day and to publish them on social media, or to share Lucretian and other relevant sources.

Today, we Hail the Hegemon and we invite all followers of Epicurean philosophy to learn about, toast, celebrate, and remember Epicurus in your own way. We wish you a pleasant Hegemon Day. Peace and Safety!

This is by Matt:

Hear these words O children of Nature’s swerve.
Let us rejoice in the freedom we desperately deserve.
Of prudent wisdom long obscured by shame.
Professed by Epicurus of noble fame.
Lucretius penned in days of old.
Across the gap of time, a truth so bold.
Arise the days of hedonic measure.
Restoring the truth of humankind’s pleasure.
Dispel the fears of death’s illusion.
Release humankind from all confusion.
Again I say, O children of Nature’s swerve.
Be frank in speech and keep your nerve.
Be ready now to strike your blow.
For Epicurus, his Garden and all who know.
The days shall come when the world will extol.
That pleasurable living was indeed the goal.

 

Non-Spoiler Review of “The Epicuriana” Novel

A Non-Spoiler Review of The Epicuriana Novel by Friend Harmonious

“I AM EPICURUS” 

The Epicuriana follows in the tradition of A Few Days in Athens, presenting itself as the reconstructed remains of a Herculaneum scroll recovered by archaeologists in the modern era. It is a fictional, historically plausible (though not always accurate), philosophical coming-of-age and romantic novel that explores the life of Epicurus primarily from his boyhood years through to later developments in his life as he travels across Ionia, amassing followers and spreading his new philosophy of tranquility and friendship.

The Good

It is deeply character-driven, exploring the intimate lives of Epicurus and those who contributed most importantly to his maturation both as a man and as a philosophical innovator, including but not limited to his father Neocles, mother Chaerestrata, and his childhood friend Servilia and her father Valerius. It includes flashback episodes to Epicurus in boyhood and concludes with a brief glimpse of Epicurus at the end of his life, and thus spans effectively his entire life.

It is clearly very well researched, drawing on a rather substantial bibliography to inform the historical plausibility of its narrative – though not completely avoiding all anachronisms and historical impossibilities.

It explores various themes such as the unpredictability of necessary and chance events, and how one’s actions as a free agent can affect dramatic changes with lasting consequences in one’s life. It touches on themes of Epicurean friendship and the love between friends (as distinct from Platonic or familial love, which are held in contrast). It explores a broad spectrum of human emotions as well as the fear of the unknown and of death.

The flow of the text certainly has the ability to evoke emotion in the reader and I found myself hooting and laughing and having other pleasant emotional responses occasionally throughout the reading of the text.

There are many interesting sequences throughout the novel, with Epicurus meeting and interacting with new characters who are pivotal to the development of the plot and of his own character. For example, there is a humorous and somewhat vicious encounter with a tag-team of Aristotelians who infiltrated the private house discussions of Epicurus and company while at Mytilene, an amusing conversation between Epicurus and the Gymnasiarch of Mytilene, and a number of adventurous episodes between Epicurus and the characters involved with the plotline of delivering Epicurus from Colophon to Lampsacus, including the captain of the ship, Master Panyotis, and a ragtag band of pirates, the latter of whom experience the fruits of Epicurus’ hoplite training skills firsthand.

One other reviewer had this to say of The Epicuriana after reading the whole work:

“[It is] A lovely personal story which mirrors the struggles and doubts of many of us today, but comes a full circle when we reflect on the past and the present. I still find it so interesting that [Epicurus’] struggles within himself, doubts, situations and successes have been repeated throughout the ages – perhaps we as people should spend time to look back at these ancient writings to learn for our future. But perhaps we are in too much of a hurry to make our own mistakes! The story really makes you think.”

The Bad

I wish that it had explored Epicurus’ friendships with Hermarchus and Metrodorus more. An individual chapter depicts a dialogue between Hermarchus and Epicurus, but the discourse was centered primarily around addressing the accusations and concerns of sexual impropriety in the Garden as advanced by the apostate Timocrates. Metrodorus is only very briefly present and his character is of singular dimension. Unfortunately, Polyaenus does not make an appearance as far as I remember, neither do any of Epicurus’ brothers (Neocles, Chaeredemus and Aristobulus), who are reported by Diogenes Laertius to have been members of the Garden School.

There are numerous minor historical anachronisms, such as the author positing that Epicurus heard the lectures of Aristotle in person in Athens, which is impossible because Aristotle had left Athens by the time Epicurus arrived, leaving his disciple Theophrastus in charge of the Lyceum (whom Epicurus may actually have heard lecture). Another glaring anachronism was evident when Epicurus was reflecting on the various philosophical schools vying for influence in the agora of Mytilene, and pauses to briefly consider the Stoics. Zeno of Citium had not started the Stoic school until a number of years after Epicurus had already established the Garden in Athens. These events (when Epicurus was still much younger and on Mytilene) being well before that time are an obvious impossibility. These inaccuracies caused me to suspend belief in some cases. The taking of certain liberties may have been deliberately chosen by the author to advance the narrative – if so, then I would view these as a disservice to the reader, as it is partly the duty of the presenter of historical fiction to clarify when they are deviating from the factual timeline.

There is also a contemporary timeline exploring the Herculaneum papyri scholars who are uncovering The Epicuriana scroll. The character relationships there are notably less interesting and fleshed-out than the ones in the ancient timeline. We only return to this timeline a few times and it may have sufficed to just leave it wholly out of the work.

The prose is impressive but is perhaps a bit too lavish in its use of rare or otherwise obscure vocabulary, especially being a contemporary piece of writing. Be prepared to have a dictionary or thesaurus near at hand to accompany the reading experience. In many cases, it would have sufficed to convey a similar meaning choosing less opulent words for the sake of the comprehensibility of the reader. It definitely interrupted the flow. These occurrences struck me somewhat as an attempt to signal the author’s own facility with language.

There is a bit too much inter-familial intrigue and melodrama for my taste, bordering close to soap opera. Without going into too much detail, it would have been tolerable if that was only central to one major plot reveal, but that’s how all the major plot reveals went.

Conclusions

I would still recommend reading A Few Days in Athens over it for an early student of Epicurean philosophy. I would only recommend The Epicuriana after one has the historical and philosophical facts clearly sorted in their mind and after having been exposed to the primary sources and the biographies by Diogenes Laertius and Norman DeWitt.

It is some pleasant and sweet fun for someone who is confident that they would be able to recognize where it goes wrong and not be susceptible to misinterpretation. I moderately recommend it.

On the Evolution of Language

The following is a commentary on the essay titled New Evidence for the Epicurean Theory of the Origin of Language: Philodemus, On Poems V, by Jacob Mackey and Epicurus, On nature, Book 28 by David N Sedley.

As we have seen before, the founders of Epicurean philosophy were deeply concerned with the role that language plays in our apprehension of the nature of things. The canonical faculty of prolepsis (anticipations) is tied to the use of language, and its place in the canon implies that language can be a shortcut to recalling things that were at one point empirically available to our other faculties. But language conventions can betray prolepsis, sometimes purposefully, as we see in the case of metaphors.

We are not necessarily against poetry. Philodemus says that poetry gives pleasure through excellence of diction and content. We may say that “mountains vomit clay into rivers”, and by context most people will know that we are speaking metaphorically. But we must never forget the utility of words in their context. This expression is fine when we speak poetically, but in his Epistle to Herodotus, Epicurus starts by saying that words are only useful if their clear meaning is kept in mind.

Epicurus clashed with Dialectitians from Megara. Among them, Diodorus Cronus (who was an extreme conventionalist), said that language isn’t natural. From these facts, we can imagine that Epicurus was arguing against them that language (and other phenomena) do exist and are natural.

Epicurus’ views concerning language evolved. He had begun adopting Metrodorus’ process of using conventional words (rather than the pedantic practice of some philosophers, who are very particular about their choice of obscure language) by the time he wrote On Nature 28:

“I now see, as I did not then, the particular difficulties concerning this class, of having correct names for individual things … as you (Metro) also used in those days to assign names without adapting certain conventional usages, so that you should not make plain the principle that by assigning any name one expresses an opinion, and see and reflect upon the indiscriminate treatment of words and objects.”

We see a distrust of words, and we see their preoccupation with avoiding the addition of opinion when we express ourselves, and a recognition of the great difficulty of this in our choice of words. We know that Lucretius mentions “opinion” as a category that does not belong in the canon. The argument here is that to name something is to express an opinion, which may be true or false. So the addition of opinion is a sign that a definition of a word is non-canonical, has no empirical basis, and is not based on true prolepsis.

In addition to these concerns, Epicurean anthropology recognizes three stages of the evolution of language.

First Stage: Nature teaches words

The founders believed that initially, language started by ananke (necessity) as a reaction to external stimuli. This view is held today by people like linguist Noam Chomsky, who has argued that there exists in the human brain an “inborn universal grammar”. But the ancients didn’t have a scientific field of linguistics. They only had empirical attestations from nature. They likely observed the role that certain calls have in certain communities of monkeys (if they came across them in their travels) or birds, who use calls to warn each other about the presence of predators, for mating, for warning enemies who enter their territory, and for other rudimentary uses. Award-winning studies of human reaction to the noise made by nails on a chalk board seem to indicate that this may an ancestral vestige of primate warning calls:

The authors hypothesized that it was due to predation early in human evolution; the sound bore some resemblances to the alarm call of macaque monkeys, or it may have been similar to the call of some predator. This research won one of the authors, Randolph Blake, an Ig Nobel Prize in 2006.

Second Stage: Reason develops language

So, the initial sounds and grunts made by our ancestors were wild, that is, invented by nature. Later, as humans became civilized, the founders argue that language was developed further by logismos (reason), which refined the first words. Since this stage is distinct from the third stage, I imagine that this stage did not involve an intellectual class, but emerged naturally from the intelligence of average language-users and from the pragmatic necessities of their interactions with each other and their environment.

Third Stage: Reason adds new discoveries

It’s in this final stage that the philosophers of the first Garden believed to be operating when they engaged in the practice of reassigning names. This is a practice that Confucian philosophers have also, interestingly, engaged in for the sake of clarity. It’s possible that this is a widespread practice among the intellectual classes of many cultures, and responds to real, universal problems of sophisticated human communication.

It’s also here that poets get to work on inventing novel ways of utilizing words, and sometimes these innovations end up having great utility, while at other times this creates confusion and obscures speech for the entire community.

Epicurus generally doubts the utility of definitions and insists that people use words as they are used commonly–and yet sometimes (as in Principal Doctrine 1, which uses the definition of the word “gods” rather than the word itself) it’s clear that he trusts the definition more than the word, because the word has been so corrupted by the culture that it’s best to clearly define it in conversation.

To the first Epicureans, the legitimate practice of word-coining was born from utility, rather than for aesthetics. When I wrote Tending the Epicurean Garden, my editor insisted that I avoid using Greek terms that no one was familiar with, and this has been a recurrent problem in the teaching mission of the Society of Friends of Epicurus, and in many of my projects of content-creation for many outlets. Rather than kinetic and katastematic, I had to refer to dynamic and abiding pleasure. Many emerging fields of scientific inquiry, new inventions, and modern media and technology, have also produced the need for many new words. This process of word-coining will never end, for as long as there is human civilization.

Further Reading:
Against the use of empty words